MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY

SCHOLASTICISM

Scholasticism is the intellectual movement of medieval Europe among the Schoolmen, that is, the teachers and leaders of the medieval universities during this period. It has been difficult to fix the bounds of this period. Some would begin the Scholastic period as early as 6th century with Boethius and extend it into the 15h century. Some would restrict Scholasticism to the period after the introduction of Aristotle into western Christian Europe. But they all agree that the high point of Scholasticism was the 12th and 13th century A.D. Among these Schoolmen were Hugo of Saint Victor (1096-1141), Peter Lombard (1100-1160), Robert Grosseteste (1168-1253), Alexander of Hales (1185-1245), and Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274). These men attempted to investigate theology and philosophy and bring into a single system the doctrines of the Christian faith and the teachings of the Greek philosophers, Plato and Aristotle. In its fullest expression this synthesis was with Aristotelianism more than with Platonism, though both philosophies were held by the Schoolmen, Platonism by the early Scholastics and Aristotelianism by the later Scholastics. The Schoolmen used a method of disputation wherein a problem was divided into parts, objection were systematically raised and answered using syllogistical logic, and the solutions to the problems were those positions that were developed during the disputation. These were gathered into Summae that were summations of theology and philosophy.
  1. Boethius.
    The Roman philosopher and statesman, Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius (A.D. c.480-524), attempted a synthesis of Hellenistic, Roman, and Christian thought, "saving" the best of old, and engendering the new. He was "the last representative of the Ancient Philosophy," according to some, and "the first of the Scholastics," by others; he belonged to the Neo-Platonic tradition and attempted the typically Platonic task of reconciling Plato and Aristotle, to the advantage of Plato, who in a sense was the founder of both the Academic and Peripatetic schools. He planed to translate the works of both Plato and Aristotle into Latin, but was able to complete only Aristotle's works on logic, the Organon, together with some commentaries on them, including Porphyry's Introduction to the Categories of Aristotle. Beothius was educated at Athens and Alexandria, and served as Consul of Rome and minister to Theodoric, Arian king of the Ostrogoths in Italy; later near the end of his life he was accused of treason and imprisoned in Italy, where he wrote his most famous work De Consolatione Philosophiae (Consolation of Philosophy), in five books, while in prison awaiting death. It is a dialogue between Boethius and "Philosophy", who leads him from despair over his situation to "the true contentment which reason united with virtue can give". It is concerned with philosophy leading the soul to God, but its failure to introduce Christianity has lead some to doubt whether he was a Christian. But this doubt can be dismissed on the basis of his other works; his De Trinitate, studying Augustine on the Trinity, a short tract on the Trinity addressed to John the Deacon, and a treatise against Eutychus and Nestorius. It is also believed that he wrote De fide catholica, which summarizes central Christian doctrines and rejects tenets of the Arians, Sabellians, and Manichaeans. About A.D. 520 he wrote the theological Tractates, known as Opuscula sacra, which established his theological authority, even to getting a commentary on it by Aquinas. His theological works were taken seriously throughout the Middle Ages, as many commentaries witness, and he was canonized. By his translations, his commentaries and his original works, Boethius bequeathed to Scholaticism much of the terminology and many of its definitions. For example, eternity as totum simul (Latin totum, "the whole, all", and simul, "at the same time") and by equating the "hypostasis" with "persona" Boethius defined "person" as "an individual substance of rational nature". In his logical works he raised the problem of the universals; he was much bolder than the logicians ( Porphyry) from whom he had received it, but he made it clear that the Aristotelian solution that he was proposing in his commentary was by no means satisfactory to him. Also in both the Trinitate the Consolation, he preferred to consider the universals as pure forms, somewhat like the Platonic Ideas. The Boethian distinction between esse (form) and id quod est (essence) is possible only if one identifies being and intelligibilty. Concerning education he wrote on the trivium (On Arithmetic) and quadrivium (On Music). Boethius is ranked among the founders of the Middle Ages because of his great influence on medieval education as well as its thought.

  2. Pseudo-Dionysius.
    This is the name given to the unknown author (a Syrian ) who at the end of the fourth or at the beginning of the fifth century A.D. (or early sixth-century) wrote a series of treatise on God and mystical theology (On the Divine Names, The Mystical Theology, The Celestial Hierarchy, The Ecclesiastical Hierarchy) and presented himself as Dionysius the Areogapite, who had been converted by the Apostle Paul's preaching on Mar's Hill in Athens (Acts 17:34). This forgery was a clever one, using a pseudonym that almost guaranteed apostolic authority. When they suddenly appeared in A.D. 532, they were not immediately accepted by everyone, but in the confused conditions of the seventh century they were gradually accepted. Erigena translated Dionysius' works into Latin about A.D. 850. By the end of the ninth century they were required reading, and the identification of their author with Dionysius the Areopagite was accepted throughout much of the Middle Ages. Lorenzo Valla first questioned their authenticity in the fifteenth century. The Reformers however called their authenticity into question and today only a few Eastern Orthodox writers still regard them as genuine. The aim of the pseudo-Dionysius was simple. He wanted to convey Neo-Platonism to an audience which would receive it only in Christian dress. He was not opposed to Christianity and probably thought that the two could be reconciled along the lines he proposed. His sincerity should not be doubted; he did not think that he was presenting a fraud but was presenting what he considered to be the truth. He was only following a received custom of the time, that employs as nom de plume a name already respected by his audience in order to win a favorable hearing. The pseudo-Dionysius believed that God could be known only by an ascent up the ladder of the celestial hierarchy. The practice of prayer and meditation would lead the seeker from one mystical experience to another, until at last he would know the transfiguration of uncreated light in a ecstatic union with the divine. The way of ascent proposed by Dionysius became the foundation of Christian mysticism and has always been opposed to dogmatic theology. The main reason for this is that the mystical experience of God, it is claimed, to be beyond human explanation. Whatever one thinks of mysticism, there can be no doubt that peudo-Dionysius' writings are a Christianized form of Neo-Platonism. The pseudo-Dionysius' mysticism depend closely on the Neo-Platonists Plotinus (A.D. 205-270) and Proclus (A.D. 410-485). Like Origen he viewed the universe as a hierarchy, descending from God who is above all beings, moving through the highest angelic spirits to the lowest material creation. He saw the heavenly pattern of this hierarchical universe reflected in the church. The "triad" of angel choirs which mediated between God and men corresponds to the "triad" of sacraments, of the orders of clergy and of the classes of "inferior Christians". In addition the three stages of spiritual life - purification, illumination and union - leads to the ultimate goal of becoming one with God Himself. The ascent through these stages consists of advances in "unknowing" - by shedding sensible and rational perceptions; illumination is by a "ray of divine darkness"; and ultimate union with God.

  3. John Scotus Erigena.
    Because of the social and political upheavals that followed after the death of Boethius, it was not until the Carolingian Renaissance that learning began again to be pursued for its own sake. In this revival of learning the most important philosopher was John Scotus Erigena (about A.D. 810-877). He was born in Ireland and educated in an Irish monastery. By A.D. 850 he was in France at the court of Charles the Bald, and teaching in the Palatine School. As a scholar, he was noted as an interpreter of Greek thought to the West. By A.D. 855 he began his translation into Latin from the Greek of the works of a Neo-Platonist known as Pseudo-Dionysius (or Denys) and the writings of the Greek theologians such as Gregory of Nyssa. As a churchman he entered into the religious controversies of his day, notably on predestination and the Eucharist. At the request of Hincmar, Bishop of Reims, he wrote a treatise, De divina praedestinatione (On Divine Predestination), against the heresy of the Augustinian monk Gottshalk. Erigena was a follower of Augustine and of the Pseudo-Dionysius and attempted to integrate a philosophic interpretation of reality with his Christianity. With Augustine he could say, "Unless you believe, you shall not understand" (Isa. 43:10 ), and thus he makes no distinction between theology and philosophy, accepting the Augustinian identification of true religion with true philosophy, with following difference: for Augustine this meant that the Christian religion contained whatever was true in philosophy because it was the truth, whereas for Erigena the Christian religion contained all truth because it was a philosophy. And that philosophy was Neo-Platonism as presented by the Pseudo-Dionysius. According to Erigena the object of philosophy is identical with that of religion. Philosophy is the science of religion, the understanding of the doctrines of religion. Philosophy and religion have the same divine content and differ in form only. Religion worships and adores, while philosophy studies, discusses, and with the aid of reason explains the object which religion adores: God, the uncreated and creative Nature. Philosophy employs the dialectic to arrive at understanding, and the dialectic was the essential method of Platonism, the ascent from individuals to generals, and the descent from the general to its species. Erigena adapted this intellectual method to formulate a concept of nature in which all things descend from their cause and are ultimately reunited with it. This gave to nature a typical hierarchical structure, which Erigena elaborated in his De Divisione Naturae (On the Division of Nature), produced about A.D. 862. Nature in the broadest sense comprises all beings, both uncreated and created things. Nature thus can be interpreted under four categories of existence:
    1. that which is uncreated and creates;
    2. that which is created and creates;
    3. that which is created and does not create;
    4. that which is uncreated and does not create.
    Existence is possible only in these four forms. But this classification may be simplified.
    The first category is, in fact, the same as the fourth, for both of them contain that which uncreated, and consequently corresponds to the only being existing in an absolute sense, that is, God. The first category embraces God in so far as He is the creative principle, the beginning or the source of all things; the fourth category is also God, but only so far as He is the end, the consummation, and the highest perfection of things.
    Upon comparing the second and third categories, we find that they form a single class, containing all created things, or the universe, in so far as this is distinct from God. The second category contains the Ideas in God, which are realized in individuals and are productive created beings. Since the Ideas have proceeded from a principle, they are subordinate to God, and can in a sense be called created. The third category contains individuals that are created but non-productive things; they are universe of things modeled on the Ideas. Hence, we have left two classes in place the four original categories: God and the created universe.

    But these two classes or modes of existence are also identical. "God is everything, and everything is God." (De Divisione Naturae, III., 17-18) "Hence we should not consider God and the creature as a duality, but as one and the same being." That is, the world is in God, and God is in the world as its essence, its soul, its life (cf. 22-23). Whatever living force, light, and intelligence the world contains, is God, who is immanent in the cosmos; and the latter exists only in so far it participates in the divine being. God is the sum-total of being without division, limit, or measure; the world is divided and limited being. God is unexplicated being; the world is explicated, revealed, manifested (theophaneia) being; God and the universe are not one and the same being, that is, two different modes or forms of the only infinite being; but rather, the world alone is a mode of being, a modification, and limitation of being, while God is being without mode of being or any determination (III, 10). This line of thought seems to lead Erigena in the direction of pantheism. But the opposite tendency in his writings can be seen in his sharp distinction he draws between God and the creation. God transcends and is superior to all differences and all contrasts; thus He cannot be designated by any term implying an opposite. We can call Him good, but incorrectly, since the difference between good and evil does not exist in Him; He is superior or above good and evil (hyperagathos, plus quam bonus est). We call Him Truth; but truth is the opposite of error, and there is no such antithesis in God. No term, not even the term being, can comprehend Him, for being is the opposite of non-being. He is higher than good, truth, and being. None of the categories of Aristotle can comprehend him, and inasmuch as to comprehend means to bring an object under a class, God Himself cannot be comprehended. He is absolute incomprehensible, the eternal Mystery.

    Erigena borrowed these affirmative and negative ways of approaching the idea of God from the Pseudo-Dionysus. The affirmative way takes some significant property of existence or life and affirms it as a property of God, for example, "God is wise." But by the negative way God is not wise. This seems like a contradiction, but in fact both propositions are true. God is wise and not-wise because He is super-wise, and so also with the other properties. God is super-wise, super-good, super-being, super-essence. God is beyond all human categories, yet the use of the positive and negative ways allows Erigena to assert the attributes of God; God is infinite being, existing in essence and eternal, changeless, etc. This lead Erigena to see that God is the essence of all things, that the world is within God, that it is both eternal and created, and that God and creatures are not distinct, the creatures emanating from God as light emanates from the sun, or heat from fire. Creation is an eternal and continuous act, an act without beginning or end. God precedes the world in dignity, not in time. God is absolutely eternal; the world is relatively eternal. Every creature is virtually eternal; our entire being is rooted in eternity; we have all pre-existed from eternity in the infinite series of causes which have produced us. The genera, species, and individuals are evolved in succession from the Infinite Being. Creation consists in the eternal analysis of the general. Being is the highest generality. From being, which is common to all creatures, which belongs only to organized beings, is separated as a special principle. Reason springs from life and embraces a still narrower class of beings (men and angels); finally, from reason are derived wisdom and knowledge (science), which belong to the smallest number. The aim of human science is to know exactly how things spring from the first causes, and how they are divided and subdivided into species and genera. Science in this sense is called dialectics, and may be divided into physics and ethics. The influence of the Pseudo-Dionysus is clear.

    The innermost essence of the human soul is as mysterious and impenetrable as God Himself, since this essence is God Himself. All that we know of it is movement and life, and that this movement, this life, has three degrees: sensation, intelligence, and reason; it is the human image of the divine Trinity. The human body was created with the soul; but it has fallen from its ideal beauty in consequence of sin. This beauty, which is latent in the actual organism, will not manifest itself in its purity except in the life to come. Man is the world in miniature, a microcosm of the universe, and as such the lord of creation. He differs from the angels only in sin, and raises himself to the level of divine being by penitence. Sin belongs to the corporeal nature of man; it is the necessary effect of the preponderance of the senses over the intellectual life in process of development. The fall of man is not only the consequence, but also the cause of his corporeal existence. The imperfections and the diseases of his actual body, his dull materiality, the antagonism between the flesh and the spirit, the difference of the sexes, all these things in themselves constitute sin, fall, separation from god, the dismemberment of the universal unity. Since there is no real being outside of God, what we call separation from god, fall or sin, is but a negative reality, a defect or privation. Evil has no substantial existence. A thing has real existence only in so far as it is good, and its excellence is the measure of its reality. Perfection and reality are synonyms. Hence absolute imperfection is synonymous with absolute non-reality; this implies the impossibility of the existence of a personal Devil, that is, an absolutely wicked being. Evil is the absence of good, life, and being. Deprive a thing of everything good in it, and you annihilate it. Through knowledge and wisdom, its culmination, the human soul rises above nature and becomes one with God. This return to God is effected for nature in general, in man; for man, in Christ and the Christian; for the Christian, in his supernatural and essential union with God through the spirit of wisdom and science. Just as everything comes from God, everything is destined to return to God. Erigena teaches predestination, that is, predestination for universal salvation. All fallen angels, all fallen men, all beings, in a word, will return to God. The punishments of hell are purely spiritual. There is no other recompense for virtue than the vision or immediate knowledge of God, no other punishment for sin than the pain of remorse. Punishments have nothing arbitrary in them; they are the natural consequences of the acts condemned by the divine law.

    Since Erigena's work On The Division of Nature was so markedly ambiguous, it was exploited by various parties; Amalric of Benes (fl. 1200 A.D.) gave a pantheistic interpretation of Erigina and Erigina's work was condemned by Pope Honorius III in A.D. 1225. The work attempts to elaborate a philosophic system which appears in places to be pantheistic, yet it emphasizes the transcendence of God in such a way that knowledge of God is almost impossible. He wished to deny that the creatures are a part of God, but he claimed, in a Neo-Platonic fashion, that God is the only true reality and the essence of things in so far as they are real. Though he was not himself a mystic, there is a strong mystic strains in his writings and provided the basis for mysticism.

  4. Anselm.
    The next really speculative thinker after Erigena is Anselm, the disciple of Lanfranc. He was born at Aosta in Italy (A.D. 1033), entered the monastery of Bec in Normandy (A.D. 1060), succeeded Lanfranc as Abbot (A.D. 1078), and as Archbishop of Canterbury (A.D. 1093). He died in A.D. 1109. He is famous for his struggle with the English kings and for his "ontological" argument for the existence of God. Anselm is Augustinian in orientation and approach, starting out from the same first principles, and sometimes he has been called the Second Augustine. Like his predecessors, Anselm makes no rigid distinction between philosophy and theology, but, like them again, his formula: fides quaerens intellectum [faith seeking to understand], implies an difference between faith (theology) and undertanding (philosophy). Like Erigena, Anselm has an enormous confidence in the ability of human reason to arrive at the truth, for, among other things, he will demonstrate the necessity of Trinity by necessary reasons. Yet, unlike Erigena, who seems to be a philosopher handling the problems of a religious metaphysics, Anselm gives the impression of a theologian using metaphysics to solve problems of Christian doctrine. He assumes that revelation and reason are in perfect accord. These two are manifestations of the one and the same Supreme Intelligence and cannot possibly contradict each other. Hence, his point of view is diametrically opposed to the point of view expressed by the phrase: credo quia absurdum est ["I believe because it is absurd"]. Indeed, Anselm saw the relation between faith and reason as expressed by the Augustinian expression: credo ut intelligam ["I believe in order to understand"]. This conviction impels him to search everywhere for arguments to support the doctrines received by revelation. As a theologian, it was his chief concern to find a simple and conclusive argument in support of the existence of God and of all of the doctrines concerning the Supreme Being. Mere affirmation did not satisfy him; he demanded proofs. This demand was continually before his mind; it caused him to forget his meals, and it pursued him even during the solemn moments of worship. He comes to the conclusion that it is a temptation of Satan, and seeks deliverance from it. But in vain. After a night spent in meditation, he discovers what he has been seeking for years; the incontrovertible argument in support of Christian doctrine, and he regards himself as blessed in having found, not only the proof of the existence of God, but his peace of soul. This proof is known as the Ontological Argument for the existence of God and is presented in the Proslogion, his most celebrated work. Anselm presents the ontological argument in two different ways:
    1. God is "that than which nothing greater can be conceived." This is idea of an absolutely prefect being, and since perfection implies existence. Hence God exists. This idea implies that the object of the thought exists, for if this idea is just an idea in the understanding, then a greater idea can be formulated of a greater being, namely of one existing not only in the understanding but also in reality.
    2. God is that which cannot be conceived not to exist. This appears to be just a negative statement of the first way, but it is really a stronger formulation of the argument. It allows one to maintain the absolute inconceivability of the divine non-existence. It allows one to assert that the phrase "the non-existence of the divine" contains a contradiction, and that the conclusion "God exists" is a necessary truth.
    The first way of putting the argument was criticized in Anselm's time by Gaunilo, a monk of Marmoutiers in Touraine, claiming that on the same ground it can be argued that a perfect island exists, since if it did not exist then any other island, really existing, would be more perfect than the perfect island in our understanding, and this would be a contradiction. Anselm answered by repeating the argument in its strict form, as given in the second way above. This seems to be Anselm's true form of the argument. Later Kant also criticized the first way of putting the argument. Kant said, "Existence is not a predicate." Nothing is added to the value of an entity by saying that it exists; there is not a penny more in value in a hundred real dollars than in a hundred possible dollars. Judging by the way Anselm answered Gaunilo, Anselm would probably have answered Kant that while Kant's analysis fits the case of all contingently existing beings it does not fit the case of the divine being, whose essence and existence are inseparably connected. God's being is necessary being, not contingent. God is that being that which cannot be conceived not to exist. If we can so much conceive of God, we must assert that He exists, and He must exist. And if we are conceiving, by our own admission, a being which may exist in our understanding alone, we are not conceiving God. In this unique case existence follows from conceivability. Since among the criteria of conceivability is consistency, the issue shifts for Anselm from God's existence to the problem of His nature. God's perfections are like human perfections; with this difference, however, that they are essential to Him, which is not the case with us. Man has received a share of certain perfections, but there is no necessary correlation between him and these perfections; it would have been possible for him not to receive them; he could have existed without them. God, on the contrary, does not get His perfections from without; He has not received them, and we cannot say that He has them; He is and must be everything that these perfections imply; His attributes are identical with His essence. Justice, an attribute of God, and God are not two separate things. We cannot say of God that He has justice or goodness; we cannot even say that He is just; for to be just is to participate in justice after the manner of creatures. God is justice as such, gooness as such, wisdom as such, happiness as such, truth as such, being as such. Moreover, all of God's attributes constitute but a single attribute, by virtue of the unity of his essence. In the rest of the Proslogion God is shown to be self-existent, creator, sensible though not a body, omnipotent, compassionate, passionless, all-knowing, supremely just, supremely compassionate, omnipresent but not existing in space and time, eternal, and unitary. The consisency of these ideas, and especially those which seem most paradoxical such as God's relation to time and space, are further explored in the Monologion. In this work Anselm sets forth his reflections on the Trinity whose image is the rational mind. There is certain natural consonance, then, that unites man and God. And man's soul being immortal, eternal blessedness is man's goal.

    But Anselm is not content with spiritualizing theism; he enumerates the difficulties which he finds in the this conception of God. God is a simple being and at same time eternal, that is, diffused over infinite points of time; He is omnipresent, that is, distributed over all points of space. Shall we say that God is ominipresent and eternal? This proposition contradicts the concept of the simplicity of the divine essence. Shall we say that He is nowhere in space and nowhere in time? But that would be equivalent to denying His existence. Let therefore reconcile these two extremes and say that God is omnipresent and eternal, without being limited by space or time. But there is also another serious difficulty: In God there is not change and consequently nothing accidental. Now, there is no substance without accidents. Hence God is not substance; He transcends all substance. Anselm is alarmed at these dangerous consequences of his logic, and he therefore prudently adds that, though the term "substance" may be incorrect, it is the best we can apply to God and that to avoid or condemn it might perhaps jeopardize our faith in the reality of the Divine Being. But the most formidable theological antinomy is the doctrine of the trinity of persons in the unity of the divine essence. The Word is the object of eternal thought; it is God in so far as He is thought, conceived, or comprehended by Himself. The Holy Spirit is the love of God for the Word, and of the Word for God, the love which God bears Himself. But is this explanation satisfactory? And does it not sacrifice the doctrine which it profeses to explain to the conception of unity? Anselm sees in the Trinity and in the concept of God insurmountable difficulties and contradiction, which the human mind cannot reconcile. In his discouragement he is obliged to confess, with Erigena, Augustine, and the Neo-Platonists, that no human word can adequately express the essence of the All-High. Even the words "wisdom" (sapientia) and "being" (essentia) are but imperfect expressions of what he imagines to be the essence of God. All theological phrases are analogies, figures of speech, and mere approximations.

  5. Universals.
    The word "universal" comes from the Latin term universalis meaning "that which pertains to all", that is, that which can be applied throughout the universe. The corresponding Greek word usually employed by Plato was eidos or "Idea". Aristotle used the Greek term to kathodou [the whole, all], which has about the same meaning as the Latin word given above. The word "universal" is related to the simple classification of words as either general or singular. A singular word refers refers to a specific object, event, or instance of quality. "Ronald Regan", "Los Angeles", "this football game", "this red here" are singular words. A general word refers to a class or kind of objects, events, or qualities. "Man", "cities", "athletics", "red color" are general words. A general word applies to each member of the class or kind. The word "man" applies to every individual man, "red color" to every occurrence of that property, "running" to every instance or event of someone running. General words are indispensible in every day human communication, as may be seen by trying to say a few sentences without them. Universals are general words. The problem of universals is concerned with the ontological status or mode of being of the referents of general words. The problem arises in connection with general words because they do not designate observable things, events, or qualities. We do not see the referents of general words, but only specific individual instants of them. For example, take the sentence, "Tom is a man." We can see Tom and we can talk to him, etc. But we do not with man. No one has ever seen man walking down the street, we only see a man, a specific individual, like Tom. If the referents of general words are not observables, then what are they? During the Middle Ages an intense debate took place about the ontological status of general words or universals. Three different solutions were proposed and defended: Realism, Conceptualism, and Nominalism.
    1. Realism holds that universals have some kind of reality outside the mind.
    2. Conceptualism holds that universals have reality only within the mind.
    3. Nominalism holds that the universals are nothing but names, and has reality neither within nor outside the mind.
    Sometimes it is difficult to distinguish between these three views, for example, some who call themselves nominalist hold not only that universals are names but also they have a reality within the mind. During the Middle Ages the problem of universals arose in a theological context. The Church was called the Catholic or universal Church; and the Church was considered to be more than an aggregation of particular Christian communities and of the believers composing them; the Church regards herself as a superior power, as a reality distinct from and independent of the individuals belonging to the fold. If the Idea, that is, the general or universal [to katholou] were not a reality, "the Church" would be a mere collective term, and the particular churches, or rather the individuals composing them, would be the only realities. Hence, the Church must be real, independent of its members; to justify this view of the church the theologians declared with the Academy: Universalia sunt realia ("Universals are real"). Thus Catholicism became synonymous with realism. Common-sense, on the other hand, tended to regard universals as mere notions of the mind, as signs designating a collection of individuals, as abstractions having no objective reality. According to common-sense, individuals alone are real, and its motto is: Universalia sunt nomina ("Universals are names"); it is nominalistic and individualistic. This nominalistic view was advanced and developed about A.D. 1090 by Roscellinus or Roscelin (A.D. 1050-1120), a canon of Compiegne. According to him, universals are "mere words", flatus vocis (the breathing of the voice), and only particular things have real existence. This thesis seemed to be quite harmless, but it was really full of heresies. If the individual alone is real, the Church is but a flatus vocis, and the individuals composing it are the only realities. If the individual alone is real, then Catholicism is no more that a collection of individual convictions, and there is nothing real, solid, and positive in the Catholic faith, but the personal faith of the individual Christian. And if the individual alone is real, then original sin is a mere phrase, and individual and personal sin alone is real. It the individual is alone is real, then there is nothing real in God except the three persons, - the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit; and the common essence which, according to the Church, unites them into one God, is a mere nomen, a flatus vocis. Roscellinus, who is especially emphatic on the latter point, is not content with defending his tritheistic heresy; he went on the offensive and accused his adversaries of heresy. The Church had condemned as a heresy the teaching called Patripassianism, that is, that the eternal Father Himself became a man in Christ and suffered and died on Calvary. Now, if the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit have the same essence, and if this essence is an objective reality, it follows that the essence of the Father or the Father Himself became man in Christ and suffered and died on Calvary; a statement that is explicitly contradicted by Scripture and the Church herself. Thus Roscellinus had pointed out a difficulty in Church dogma, - an offense for which the Church never forgave him. The Council of Soissons condemned his heresy and forced him to retract it (A.D. 1092). Nominalism thus anathematized became quiesecent for more than two centuries, and did not reappear until about A.D. 1320, in the teachings of William of Ockham. The most ardent champions of realism in the controversy aroused by Roscellinus were Anselm and William of Champeaux.

    Anselm combated not only the dogmatic heresy but also the philosophical heresy, namely, the negation of Platonic realism. He says, speaking of the nominalists, "They cannot understand that man is something more than a individual." Anselm followed the Augustinian tradition, holding to the reality of universals both in sensible things and in the mind of God. It was Anselm who accused Roscellinus of holding that the universal is a "mere word", flatus vocis. In arguing against Roscellinus, Anselm seems to have held that there is but one substance or nature in all men.

    William of Champeaux (A.D. 1070-1120), a professor at Paris and afterwards Bishop of Chalons, adopted an extreme form of realism, the identity theory of universals. According to this view, nothing is real but the universal; individual are mere flatus vocis. Looking at man, there is in reality but one man, the universal man, the man-type, the genus man. All individuals are fundamentally the same, and differ only in the accidental modifications of their common essence. Champeaux is but a step away from pure pantheism, and yet he is the defender of orthodoxy, the passionate adversay of the heresy of Roscellinus! Abelard criticized this position on the grounds that if it were true the same substance would exist in more than one place at the same time; Socrates is really Plato, and occupies two places simultaneously. If Man were in Plato and Plato were in Rome, then since Man is also in Socrates, Socrates must also be in Rome. In addition what we say of any two members of a species can also be said of God. Since God is a substance, then He is, on this view, identical with all that is, so that one consequence of this view is pantheism. In response to these criticisms Champeaux shifted to an indifference theory of universals. The individual members of a species, he now held, are not the same essentially. But they are the same indifferently. This meant that the essences of the individual members of a species are similar, and this similarilty provides the basis for the concept of the species which applies indifferently to all of its members. On this view the essence or nature of any two things of the same species are numerically different, although alike in resulting same properties.

    Between extreme realism, which says: Universale ante rem ("Universal is before the thing"), and extreme nominalism, which has the motto: Universale post rem ("Universal is after the thing"), there is a mediating position, which may be summarized as follows: Universale neque ante rem nec post rem, set in re ("Universal is neither before the thing, nor after the thing, but in the thing"). This is conceptualism, the position set forth by Abelard.

    Peter Abelard or Pierre Abailard, was born in Palais (Pallet), near Nates in Brittany, France (A.D. 1079) and studied at Paris sucessively under Roscellinus and Willam of Champeaux, who was the most skilful controversialist of the period. Quarrelling with his teacher, who was jealous of his pupil's brilliant talents, Abelard, though only twenty-two years of age, opens a school at Melun, then at Corbeil. His reconciliation with Champeaux brought him back to Paris, where he is met with unparalleled success as a teacher. He falls victim to the vindictiveness of the canon of Notre Dame, Fulbert, whose teenage niece Heloise he had seduced, and retires to the Abbey of St. Denis, while Heloise takes the veil at the convent of Argenteuil. In his retirement he writes the treatise De trinitate, a work which brings down upon his head the wrath of the Church. The Council of Soissons condemns him unheard and his book was delivered to the flames (A.D. 1121). At Nogent-sur-Seine he founded an Oratory, which he dedicated to the Trinity, and particularly to the Paraclete. This he afterwards surrendered to Heloise, in order to enter upon his duties as Abbot of St. Gildas de Ruys. Denounced as a heretic by Bernard of Clairvaux, he is again condemned, this time by the Council of Sens to imprisonment (A.D. 1141). On his way to Rome to appeal his case to Pope Innocent II, he finds an unexpected refuge in the Abbey of Cluny, and a noble protector in Peter the Venerable, through whose efforts Bernard is finally moved to forgive him. These difficulties undermine his health, and cause his death in A.D. 1142.

    As a result of Abelard's criticism of William of Champeaux, Abelard's position on universals seems to be not very different from the position to which he forced Champeaux, although Abelard approaches the problem in manner of Roscellinus. But Abelard is too much a realist to accept the views of Roscellinus, and too much a nominalist to subscribe to the theory of William of Champeaux. According to Abelard, the universal exists in the individual; outside the individual it exists only in the form of a concept. Moreover, though it exists in the individual as a reality, it exists there not as an essence but as an individual. If it existed in it as an essence, or, in other terms, if it exhausted the essence of the individual, what would be the difference between Peter and Paul? Although Abelard's view is not identical with nominalism, it comes very near it. It is to the ultra-realistic doctrine of Champeaux what the concrete realism of Aristotle is to the abstract realism of Plato. Abelard, who was not acquainted with Aristotle's Metaphysics, was able to understand its content from the few hints he get from the Organon. Abelard had produced a compromise between nominalism and realism, which was in effect a rediscovery of Aristotelianism. This alone would assure him a high place among the doctors of the Middle Ages.

    To summarize: Abelard's position on universals includes the following points.

    1. When names are predicated to things; these names are either universal or particular names. When one says that Plato is a man or is tall or old, the predicate name is a universal name, man, or particular name, tall or old.
    2. The predicate names are not things or res, as realism claims. Since things, like stars and stones, cannot be predicates (we do not say "the heavy is stone" or "the old is Plato"), realism which claims that the predicates are things or res must be rejected. Neither are they a mere words, flatus vocis, or sounds, as nominalism claims. The predicate cannot be a mere word, for a word or sound is a thing just as much as a stone is. The predicate therefore is not a vox, but, to invent a new term, it is a sermo. It is something that carries a significance; and this significance or meaning is the predicate.
    3. The process by which the mind produces the significance, determines the nature of universals. If we think of Plato, we have in mind a singular substance, an individual thing, Plato as Plato. But if we think that Plato is old or is a man, we have limited our attention to this or that aspect of Plato. We no longer think of Plato as Plato, but as a man; that is, we think of his rationality by which he belongs to a certain species, the rationality that distinguishes him from other animals. Or we may think of his being old, or of some other quality which he has in common with other things. This process of selection or abstraction results in a concept. The common quality therefore becomes a predicate when it is abstracted and applied. It is not a thing in nature like an individual, though it has it basis in the individual and is not just an empty sound. Thus the predicate is in one sense in the thing, and in another sense it is in our mind. In this sense Abelard is also willing to say with the realist that universals are eternally in the mind of God. Conceptualism therefore is intended to salvage the elements of truth that were in other theories without their indefensible flaws.
    Abelard agrees with Anselm that revealed truth and rational truth are identical, but he does not, like Anselm, accept Augustine's credo ut intelligam. In his Introductio ad theologiam [Introduction to Theology], he condemns "the presumptuous credulity of those who indiscriminately and hastily accept any doctrine whatsoever before considering its merits and whether it is worthy of belief." He was an enthusiastic admirer of Greek philosophy, which, however, he himself confesses, he knows only from the works of Augustine. He finds all the essential doctrines of Christianity, its conception of God, the Trinity, and the incarnation, in the great thinkers of antiquity, and the distance between Paganism and Gospel does not seem so great to him as that between the Old and the New Testaments. From the ethical point of view, he believes that Greek philosophy has the advantage over the teachings of the Old Testament. Hence, why should we deny the pagan thinkers eternal happiness because they did not know Christ? What is the Gospel but a reform of the natural moral law? Shall we consign people to hell "whose lives and teachings are truly evangelical and apostolic in their perfection, and differ in nothing or very little from the Christian religion"?

    How does Abelard manage to find the doctrine of Trinity in Greek philosophy? By reducing the three persons to the three essential attributes (proprietates non essentiae) of the Divine Being: power, wisdom, and goodness. Taken separately, he says, these three properties: power, knowledge, and will, are nothing; but united they constitute the highest perfection (tota perfectio boni). The Trinity is the Being who can do what he wills, and who wills what he knows to be the best. From the theological stand-point, this is monarchism, a heresy opposed to the tritheism of Rosellinus. Philosophically, it is concrete spiritualism, which denies that force and thought are separate entities, and holds that they are united in the will.

To continue, click here.