Since Christianity is a religion centering in the person and work of Jesus Christ, it is not a philosophy. For a philosophy is an intellectual construction resulting from the human intellectual activity that is called philosophy. Christianity is neither a human intellectual construction - a philosophy - nor the human intellectual activity of philosophy. That this is so can be seen by investigating the nature of philosophy and its differences from religion and its relation to religion and to Christianity in particular.
The term "philosophy" comes from two Greek words, philein, to love and sophia, wisdom. The Greek philosopher Pythagoras (c. 572-497 B. C.) is said to have called himself a lover of wisdom. Socrates (c. 470-399 B. C.) refused to call himself a sophist, that is, one who has wisdom, but only a philosopher, a lover of wisdom. Philosophy therefore is not wisdom, but only the love or desire for wisdom, implying thereby the pursuit of wisdom rather than its attainment.
What is wisdom? In modern times the word wisdom has been restricted almost entirely to practical wisdom; it denotes an insight which applies knowledge to life and action and connotes a manner of life based on understanding and experience. In earlier times (Plato and Socrates) wisdom was taken to include both theoretical and practical wisdom. Later philosophers (Aristotle and Aquinas) limited the concept of wisdom to a kind of knowledge that gives understanding and insight into the meaning of the whole of reality. This speculative or theoretical wisdom was distinguished from and contrasted with "prudence" which was the name they gave to practical wisdom.
Philosophy is the search for this wisdom. Accordingly philosophy may be defined as that human intellectual activity which aims at the acquisition of a body of general and systematic knowledge concerning those aspects of reality characteristic of it as a whole in order to understand the whole of reality. An analysis of this definition will disclose three important characteristics of philosophy.
In conclusion, the body of knowledge that philosophy seeks to give understanding of the whole of reality may be called theoretical wisdom. The ability to bring this theoretical wisdom to bear upon the problems and tasks of life may be called practical wisdom. Philosophy as an intellectual activity is the search for wisdom and a philosophy as an intellectual construct is the wisdom sought. [4]
Philosophy differs from religion formally in three respects. Since Christianity is a religion, it differs formally from philosophy in the same three respects that other religions differ from philosophy. [5]
Thus religion and Christianity as a religion differs from philosophy. But although religion and philosophy are formally different, this does not mean that they are unrelated. On the contrary, there is a positive twofold relationship between philosophy and religion. This relation consists of more than just the fact that they are both human activities and are concerned with reality. This positive twofold relationship may be stated in the following way: philosophy has a religious foundation, and religion has philosophical implications. [7]
From these two considerations it appears that philosophy is involved with, grounded in, and carried on consciously or unconsciously from within the confines of a religious commitment. [9]
The elaboration and clarification of the philosophic implications of the
Christian ultimate commitment to Jesus Christ and to God the Father through
him is called a Christian philosophy. The Christian ultimate commitment
implies a definite view of the world or reality. This view of reality which
is contained in the Hebrew-Christian Scriptures makes the fundamental
ontological distinction between the Creator and the creation (Gen. 1:1; Isa.
40:28; Acts 17:24; Rev. 4:11). God the Father is the creator of all things
that are not-God through Jesus Christ, His Son (I Cor. 8:6; Col. 1:16; Heb.
1:2; John 1:3). This Christian world view gives a certain character to the
whole of reality. All that is real is created by God the Father through Jesus
Christ, His Son, except God Himself (John 1:3). Also God freely
created all things (Rev. 4:11). All that is not-God is the free creation of
God. He was under no compulsion or necessity to create. There was no inner
necessity in God which required that He create to fulfill a lack or need.
Even though all of creation is dependent upon God for its existence, God is
not dependent upon anything. In addition, the creation is neither an
emanation nor a part of God; it neither came out of God nor did it eternally
exist as a part of God. Finally, all creation is good. Although not-God, the
creation is not evil; it is good but not ultimate good. It is good because God
created it and recognized that it was good.
"And God saw everything he had made, and, behold, it was very good"
(Gen. 1:31; see also Gen. 1:4, 10, 12, 18, 21, 25).
This character of reality given in the Christian world view implies a
definite position with regard to those aspects of reality characteristic of it
as a whole, such as being, value, and knowledge. A Christian philosophy is the
intellectual expression of this position. Thus a Christian philosophy may be
defined as an intellectual construction which contains the elaboration and
clarification of the philosophic implications of the Christian ultimate
commitment to Jesus Christ and to God His Father through Him.
In conclusion, although Christianity is not a philosophy, there is a definite positive relationship between Christianity and philosophy. As a religion Christianity sustains the same positive two sided relation with philosophy as any other religion:
[1] See W. H. Werkmeister, The Basis and Structure of Knowledge (New York: Harper & Brothers Publishers, 1948) p. 3f. This definition is intended as a working definition, not as a solution of the problem of knowledge.
[2] See Irving M. Copi, Symbolic Logic (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1954) pp. 167-181. The general and systematic character of scientific knowledge is what distinguishes it from common everyday knowledge like that in a telephone book.
[3] The word "reality" is used here to refer to that which is as contrasted to that which is fictitious, imaginary or illusionary. The word is not intended to indicate the ontological position of any philosophy nor to offer a solution to the problem of being.
[4] The definition of philosophy given above is partially inadequate because it fails to make any reference to the methodological character of the intellectual activity we have here called philosophy. This intellectual activity is not haphazard. It proceeds according to a definite method called the philosophical method. This method is very much similar to the scientific method. In fact, it is the scientific method as applied to the subject matter of philosophy. An explanation of the scientific method and its application to subject matter of philosophy will be set forth in the next chapter.
[5] In the following comparison between philosophy and religion the formal differences are stressed; that is, the differences of form between them. This does not mean that they are unrelated. On the contrary, there is a definite positive twofold relationship between them as will be pointed out below.
[6] "The essence of philosophy is to think; the essence of
religion is to dedicate. Each is more an undertaking that a
subject of study. A good course in philosophy does not
merely teach students about philosophy; far more
significantly, it teaches them to philosophize.
Those who promote religion are never satisfied with imparting
information about religion; they are concerned, instead,
that people be religious. Philosophy and religion, both,
seek knowledge, but they seek knowledge for different
purposes."
[Trueblood, op. cit., pp. 8-9. Italics are his.]
He goes on to quote from William Temple,
Nature, Man and God
(London: Macmillan Company, 1934), p. 30.
"Philosophy seeks knowledge for the sake of understanding,
while religion seeks knowledge for the sake of worship."
[7] John A. Hutchison, Faith, Reason, and Existence
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1956) pp. 28-29.
[8] "In thinking, no beginning can be made without assumptions. No matter how basic the problem, there is not [sic] absolute starting point behind which there remains nothing to be defined." [Marten Ten Hoor, "The Role of the Philosopher," Philosophical Review, LVI (1947), p.510.]
[9] One objection that might be raised against this
presentation of the religious foundation of philosophy is
that it involves philosophy in pure subjectivism.
Philosophy, according to this point of view, becomes just
the instrument for the expression of the philosopher's
personal interests and prejudices. This objection overlooks
the fact that philosophy is the intellectual activity of a
person, a self. "Reasoning never occurs in the abstract.
It is always the activity of an individual mind. It can
never be separated from the crucial experience of a
particular living person." [Edward Thomas Ramsdell, The
Christian Perspective (New York: Abingdon-Cokesbury Press,
1950), p.31] But even though philosophy is subjective in the
good sense of that term as any other human activity, it is
not purely subjective. For every subjective decision of a
person has objective reference if it is not whimsical or
arbitrary. "The value judgments which free choice entails
are 'objective' in the sense that they refer to a standard
of good and evil independent of oneself. They are
distinguished from private inclinations and tastes by the
fact that this external criterion can overrule personal
preferences. If a man's value judgments are consequent upon
the particular standard which he adopts, and if he cannot
make a responsible decision without reference to it, the
conclusion is that the very exercise of freedom necessarily
involves the agent in a relation to something beyond himself."
[E. La B. Cherbonnier, Hardness of Heart
(Garden City, New York: Doubleday & Company, Inc., 1955), p. 39]
Philosophy, ancient and modern, has either overlooked or
ignored this relation (see E. La B. Cherbonnier, Ibid., pp. 45-48).
The subject is not without its object in the sense
of an external criterion and standard of good and evil.
When this object is the subject's ultimate criterion, it is
his god and the subject's commitment and devotion to it is
his religion.
[10] "A reader of the higher class of works in German
theology - especially those that deal with the philosophy of
religion - cannot fail to be struck with the constant
recurrence of a word for which he finds it difficult to find
a precise equivalent in English. It is the word
'Weltanschauung,' sometimes interchanged with another
compound of the same signification, 'Weltansicht.' Both
words mean literally 'view of the world,' but whereas the
phrase in English is limited by associations which connect
it predominantly with the physical nature, in German the
word is not thus limited, but has almost the force of a
technical term, denoting the widest view which the mind can
take of things in the effort to grasp them together as a whole
from the standpoint of some particular philosophy or theology."
[James Orr, The Christian View of God and the World
(Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1947) p. 3]
[11] "Whatever a man worships as the supremely important defines his perspective." [Edward Thomas Ramsdell, op. cit., pp. 32, 33. Italics are his.]
[12] Many philosophers use the terms "world-view" and "philosophy" synomymously (cf. Brightman, Kattsoff). This seems to me to lead to much confusion. A philosophy (in distinction from philosophy as an intellectual activity) is an intellectual construction about those aspects of the whole of reality which are characteristic of it as a whole such as knowledge, value and being. A philosophy is the result of an intellectual activity, whereas a world-view is the point of view given with one's ultimate commitment. Thus to use these terms interchangeably is to confuse these two very different things. This, however, is not intended to deny that there is a positive relation between them. The character given to the whole of reality by a world-view implies a definite position with regard to those aspects of the whole of reality which are characteristic of it as a whole. This position comes to intellectual expression in a philosophy. For further discussion on this point see H. A. Durfee, op. cit., footnote 10, p. 197.