THE PROBLEM OF THE GOOD

    Martin Luther
    Martin Luther insisted, in opposition to all egocentric form of religion, upon a purely theocentric religion. Whatever the subject he dealt with, the idea of justification, the Lord's supper, etc., he opposed the egocentric tendency. In his campaign against Catholic Christianity, Luther is governed by this opposition. In catholic piety, he finds the egocentric tendency; there everything centers upon man himself, what he does and what happens to him. Salvation which is God's own work, which God has reserved to Himself alone and accomplished through Christ, is transformed into a work of man; righteousness is transformed from something that God gives into something man achieves. Obedience to God is transformed by the idea of merits into that which yields profit for man. Everything is measured by the standard of human desire and by the importance it has for man. This even applies to God Himself. When God is extolled as the highest good, summum bonum, it is as man's highest good. Luther's main objection to Catholic piety is always this, that it puts man's own self in the place of God. Luther sees himself to be the herald of theocentric religion in his campaign against all egocentricity. This is expressed with clarity in the manifesto which he introduces his lectures on Romans (1515-1516). He declares that there is something which is to be broken down and destroyed, and something contrary which is to be built up and planted. And what is to be broken down and destroyed is everything "that is in us," all our righteousness and wisdom, absolutely everything in which we take a selfish delight. What is to be built up and planted is "everything that is outside us and in Christ." The righteousness by which God saves us, is not produced by us, but has come to us from outside us; it is not derived from earth, but has come to us from heaven. Luther observed that the whole Catholic doctrine of love displays an egocentric perversion. However much Catholic piety speaks of God's love, the emphasis is primarily placed on the love we owe to God. The love of God is less God's love for us than our love for God. Love is regarded essentially as a human achievement. In the Catholic presentation love never loses the marks of acquisitive love and this can be traced logically back up to self-love. In contrast to Catholic piety, Luther sets a thoroughly theocentric idea of love. When Luther speaks about love in the Christian sense, he draws not from the realm of human love at all, but from God's love, especially as this has been revealed in Christ. And this love is not acquisitive love, but a love that gives. This is seen especially when Luther speaks about justification. In his famous autobiographical fragment with which he prefaced the Latin edition of his complete works in 1545, Luther speaks of Rom. 1:17 where he made the discovery that changed his understanding of the righteousness of God. Justification is not a question of the "iustitia" [righteousness] in virtue of which God makes demands upon us, but the "iustitia" which God bestows, so Christian love is not concerned with the love with which we love God, but with the love with which God Himself loves. God's righteousness is the righteousness that God gives [dono], and not the righteousness that God requires. Luther uses here the scholastic distinction between active and passive righteousness, rejecting the righteousness of God in the active sense, but accepting it in the passive sense.

    Luther was fully aware of the revolutionary nature of his message. He knows that by it he is pronouncing judgment not only upon Catholic "work-righteousness," but upon "all religions under heaven." Here there is no difference between Jews, Papists and Turks; in all of them he find the same religious attitude. All false religions are characteristic by the same reasoning: "If I do this and that, God will be gracious to me." Ultimately, there is only two religions, that which is built on faith in Christ, and that which is buildt on reason and one's own works. These are absolutely opposed to each other; if we can deliver ourselves from sin and enter by our righteousness into heaven; then Christ is superfluous. Thus Christianity is bound to regard these false religions as its adversaries. These religions are man's attempt to climb up to heaven and is counter to the message that God came down from heaven in Christ and offered eternal life as gift to be received by faith. This message destroys all false religions that attempts to earn eternal life by the merits of their righteous works. It demolishes all false, egocentric religions.

    To understand Luther at this point, we must look at their view of man. Luther rejects the view of man that his nature has a higher and lower part, as having a "spiritual" and a "carnal" nature. For Luther the natural man is "fleshly" in his whole being, in all that he does and is. Not merely the sensible part of man, not merely what his "fleshly" nature makes him do, but also the highest and best in him, and primarily this is "flesh." Even his righteousness, his religion, and works belong to the "flesh." Even when he is saved, being justified by faith, the Christian is "simultaneously righteous and a sinner" [simul iustus et peccator]. God justifies the sinner as righteous in such way that the sinner remains a sinner. It is this assertion of Luther's that the sinfulness of man remains even in the justified man, that has caused offense in Catholic circles.

    The medieval interpretation of Christianity is marked by the upward way to God. This is asserted not only in the legalistic piety of popular Catholicism, but also in the rational theology of Scholasticism and the ecstatic religiosity of Mysticism. These are three ways or ladders by which man climb up to God. Against these three ways of ascent, Luther makes his protest. He will have nothing to do with this "climbing up into the majesty of God." At the center of Luther's protest is his rejection of the way of merit. The "good works" that Catholicism promotes are not really good works because they performed for the wrong intention. The general Catholic view is that an work is good and meritorious before God, only when it is done with the intention of obtaining eternal blessedness. It is this intention, this motive, which according to Luther robs it of its value; even makes it condemnable. The one who does the good in order to win "merits" and to promote his blessedness is not wholly devoted to the good itself. He is only using it as a means for climbling up to the Divine Majesty. Only when this intention is rooted out, and the good is done "to the glory of God and the benefit of our neighbor," is it really good at all. Thus Luther rejected the idea of good works as a ladder to heaven. Luther equally rejects all attempts to ascend to God by the way of reason and speculation. He himself tried this way during his time in the monastery. One of the books he took as his guide at that time was Bonaventura's Itinerarium mentis in Deum. From it he learned of the ascent by the analogical ladder of speculation. Later he rejected any attempt "to climb up to heaven by thinking" because it is doomed to failure. The Way of speculation is impassable as was the Way of merit. If God is to be known, it is only if God chooses to reveal Himself; otherwise, God is unknowable. And God has chosen to reveal Himself in the Incarnation of the Word; in the Incarnation, God has descended to us. At the manger of Bethlehem, the Way of reason is exposed as false and vain. Reason in its attempt to ascend to heaven does not get God but only its idea of God. It is not the truth that the Way of reason reaches, but just speculation. Luther's objections to the attempt to ascend up to God by the ladders of merit and of speculation are also applicable to the mystical Way of ascent. Luther rejects the interpretation of the passage of Scripture that has been taken by mysticism for its support, Matt. 5:8:
    "Blessed are the pure of heart, for they shall see God."
    This Scripture seems to point to the mystical experience of seeing God (visio Dei) as the final goal of the Christian life. Does it not speak of purification as the way to that goal, much as Plato speaks of purification which is necessary in order to reach the vision of the self-subsistent Being and Beauty. But Luther will not accept this interpretation. He explains this text not according to an ascent to God, but according to God's descent.

    "Thou mayest not climb up to heaven nor run into a cloister after it.... But that is a pure heart, which looks and thinks upon what God says."
    And the vision spoken of this text has nothing to do with mystical Vision of God.
    "To see His face, as the Scripture says,
    means rightly to perceive Him as gracious, good Father,
    to whom we may look for all good things.
    But this only comes through faith in Christ."
    Another passage of Scripture that mysticism used in proclaiming the Way of mysticism is the story of the heavenly ladder which Jacob saw in his dream (Gen. 28), Luther rejected the interpretation of this passage as teaching that the heavenly ladder is the ladder of mysticism. God has not commanded us to raise a ladder up to heaven to come to Him; God Himself has provided the ladder and has come down to us. In Christ, God has come down to meet us; Christ is the heavenly ladder and the "Way" furnished by God (John 14:6).

    The one subject on which Luther and Augustine seem to be in agreement is that self-love is the root of all evil. Augustine stresses this emphatically, especially in the The City of God [De civitate Dei], when he traces the opposition between the kingdom of God and the kingdom of the world back to that between love of God [amor Dei] and love of self [amor sui]. But this self-love refers to "inorderd" [inordinata] self-love, which seeks its satisfaction in something other than God, in temporal and transient things. In addition to the perverted self-love, Augustine speaks of a right self-love, which seeks its satisfaction in God Himself. This sort of self-love is so far from being opposed to love for God, that it is equivalent to it. Thus for Augustine, sin is obviously not self-love as such, but only its wrong direction that is sin and the root of sin; Augustine is using another criterion of sin. This other criterion that Augustien finds is the idea that is linked with sensible and material things. As man's nature is at once both spiritual and sensible, man is a citizen of two worlds. By God's appointment man has the highest good in him. Man should direct his thoughts and desires up towards the super-sensible, spiritual world. But now man's sensible side of his being offers resistance, and seeks to drag man down and puts him in bonage to temporal goods. Hence, when Augustine wishes to characterize the sinful man, he says that man is "curvatus." He is not, as he ought to be, erect and looking upwards, but crooked, bent down to the earth.

    Luther's view is the direct antithesis to these ideas of Augustine. When Luther calls selfishness, self-love, as sin and as the essence of sinfulness of sin, Luther means what he says without any qualification. Luther knows no good self-love. In the commandment: "Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself," Augustine had actually held that a commandment of self-love was implied, even if it is not expressly stated by a separate commandment. Luther, on the contrary, asserts that the Commandment of Love involves the rejection and condemnation of all self-love whatsoever. On the basis of Christ's words in John 12:25

    ("He who loves his life will lose it,
    and he hates his life in this world
    shall keep it to eternal life."),
    Luther takes as a fundamental principle:
    "To love is the same as to hate oneself."
    Earlier in the lectures on Romans, Luther says that there are two interpretations of the commandment to love of one's neighbor are possible. It may be taken to mean that both things are commanded, to love one's neighbor and to love oneself. Or it can be understood so that only love of our neighbor is commanded, while the manner in which we love ourselves is the pattern of our love for our neighbor. Luther adds the comment that this latter interpretation please him better. He later declares that the intrepretation that has prevailed since Augustine is false. In commanding man to love his neighbor as himself, God is in no way commanding that man shall love himself. Self-love is a vicious love, which must be destroyed. Nevertheless, it can serve as a pattern for the right kind of love to our neighbor, just as Adam is type of Christ.
    "Just as in Adam we are evil, so in Christ we ought to be good."
    Similarly, Jesus uses sinful self-love as an example of how we ought to love our neighbor. Thus Luther finds in the commandment to love one's neighbor as one's self, a prohibition of every kind of self-love; even deliverance from self-love.

    When stating what man's corruption is, Luther uses Augustine's expression: man is crooked or "bent" (curvatus). But Luther uses it in a different sense than Augustine. When Augustine says that man is "bent," "crooked" (curvus, curvatus), he meant that man's desires are bent down to the things of earth, that he loves and pursues the lower, temporal things. Luther took it to mean that man has a selfish disposition and he is bent back on himself. In other words, the will is not straight, but "crooked," turned back to itself. Luther's concept of sin is governed by self-love. When Paul wrote, "Love seeks not its own" (I Cor. 13:5), Luther sees that sin is the opposite of this; the essence of sin is that man seeks its own self. And since the whole of natural human life is governed by this principle, all humanity is under the dominion of sin. Sin has its seat not merely in man's sensible nature, but it embraces the whole man. And furthermore sin is not just evil acts of men, but permeates the greatest and most praiseworthy deeds; for they are done for man's own glory. Even the very highest that man can attain, that is, fellowship with God, is polluted by this egocentricity. It is this that arouse Luther's hostility to Catholic piety, in which the attainment of this highest good is reduced to a system to obtain it. And it was this Augustinian and Medieval view of self-love as the Way of Salvation that Luther opposed; it must be plucked up by the roots, if true love is takes its place.

    The culmination of Luther's attack on Catholic piety is the removal of love outside the context of justification entirely and elimination of the Catholic idea of "fides caritate formata" [faith formed by love] which asserts that man is justified by faith and love. That is, the decisive thing for man's justification is not faith but love, Charitas. In the Aristotelian thought, the form of a thing is what gives to matter its reality and value. So love, Charitas, is what gives to faith its reality and value. Faith is the matter, and as such is insubstantial and powerless. Love is the form, the formative principle, that gives to faith its worth and real being. So justification is ultimately not by faith, but by love, Charitas, that man is justified and comes into fellowship with God.
    In opposition, Luther asserted that justification takes place by faith alone, "sola fide." When Luther read in Paul:
    "a man is justified by faith, without the works of the law,"
    he found not merely a rejection of salvation by meritorious works, but the rejection of salvation by love. Justification is not only not by outward works of the law, but also and especially not by love, which is the fulfilling of the law. This teaching has been misunderstood that Luther has set love aside as unimportant and that he was asserting the importance only of faith; and that he had replaced the "religion of love" with a "religion of faith." From the Catholic point of view, Luther has been regarded as the destroyer of the Christian idea of love. Though most Evangelicals do not agree with this judgment, they regard Luther's treatment of love as the weakest point in his thought, and his polemical position has pushed love too much into the background. Some Evangelicals think that Luther's preoccupation with his religious task has caused him to forget about the ethical side of Christianity. Although his emphasis on "sola fide" is his religious strength, it is considered to be the source of his ethical weakest, in so far as it caused him to separate, not only the works of love, but love itself, from the basic relationship to God. That "Love has had to stand down in favor of faith" is the almost universal view in this matter.

    But Luther is not the destroyer of the Christian idea of love, but the destroyer of the wrong idea of Christian love that dominated Catholic piety. The Catholic idea of love is a distortion of the Christian idea of love. And Luther is not neglecting the ethical side of Christianity by emphasizing "sola fide" but is the restoring the true basis for the ethical side of Christianity. Luther is rejecting the idea that man's relationship to God is based on the good that he does and is, that is, on man's love and his works of love. It is this idea that Luther is rejecting in his emphasis on justification by faith alone. Luther is not setting faith against love, but is asserting the correct relationship of faith to love. It is not our love for God that justifies us, but God's love for us that justifies us through faith receiving that love. Luther understood love as nothing other than God Himself; thus Luther can say of the man who abides in love, "that he and God become one cake [eine Kuche]". Luther had no intention to minimize and depreciate love. In rejecting the Scholastic doctrine of "fides caritate formata" Luther is rejecting the idea that it is our love for God that justifies us. By "justification by faith alone" Luther does not mean that it is our faith, our believing, that justifies us, but by our faith we receive the righteousness that God in His love has provided for us in Christ. We are justified not by our righteousness but by God's righteousness. To preach faith in Christ is nothing other than to preach love, that is, God's love. Through faith we are the children of God, and we love by the love we have received. This is the true basis for the ethical side of Christianity. Luther also rejects the idea of grace of Catholic piety as the enablement of God through the sacraments to do the good works by which the Christian can merit eternal life. He understood God's grace as God's unmerited favor, whereby God provides the righteousness that we need.

    Christianity is a religion of love. Luther's opposition and criticism of Catholic piety and theology was directed against its nisunderstanding of love. His problem with Catholic piety was its understanding of love as egocentric, self-centered love. Luther's understanding of love was the direct antithesis of Augustine ideas of love. Augustine understood all love to be acquisitive love, which seeks its satisfaction in something. Augustine distinguishes between perverted self-love and right self-love; perverted self-love is directed to the temporal and transient things, seeking to find its satisfaction in something other than God. This sort of self-love is opposed to love for God, which seeks its satisfaction in God, as its summun bonum. Luther rejected this understanding of love, which came to dominate Catholic piety. Luther brands all self-love as sin; he held that self-love is the essence of the sinfulness of sin. Luther argued that all love that is not centered in God, not theocentric, is evil, and it is wrong to call it "love":
    "To love is the same as to hate oneself"
    [Est enim diligere se ipsum odisse].

    Anders Nygren
    Anders Nygren in his classic work, Agape and Eros, has given a thorough historical analysis of the two "fundamental motifs" or themes that have dominated the understanding of love in Western philosophy and theology. He raises the problem of "Agape and Eros", and finds its natural solution in the Reformation. We have summarized Nygren's historical treatment above. The problem of "Agape and Eros" is: What is the true Christian idea of love? Is it Eros or Agape, or a synthesis of these? Nygren answers that the true Christian idea of love is Agape, which is theocentric in contrast to Eros which is egocentric. This may be seen clearly when the two fundamental questions is asked of Christainity: the religious question, "What is God?" and the ethical question, "What is the Good, the Good-in-itself?" To the religious question Christainity replies with the Johannine statement: "God is agape" (I John 4:8, 16); and to the ethical question the answer is similar: "The Good is agape", and this ethical answer is summarized in the Commandment of Love, the commandments to love God and to love one's own neighbor (Matt. 22:36-40; Mark 12:28-34). According to Nygren, Christian Agape has no relation to Hellenistic Eros, even when Agape is compared to the "heavenly Eros" and not with the Vulgar Eros. The heavenly character of Agape is clear; there is no need to spiritualize or sublimate it to recognize its heavenly character. With Eros it is otherwise; but the highest form of Eros, Eros in the most spiritual form, the "heavenly Eros", cannot begin to compete with Agape. The mistake, Nygren says, that is commonly made is to represent

    "Agape as a higher and more spiritualised form of Eros, and supposing that the sublimation of Eros is the way to reach Agape... The heavenly Eros is the highest possible thing of its kind; it has been spiritualised to an extent beyond which it is impossible to go. Agape stands alongside, not above, the heavenly Eros; the difference between them is not of degree but of kind. There is no way, not even that of sublimation, which leads from Eros to Agape." [52] [1]

    Nygren attempts to describe the content of the Christian idea of love, Agape. The following is his summary of its main features.

    1. Agape is "spontaneous" and "unmotivated". By "spontaneous" Nygren means that there is no necessity in Agape, no extrinsic ground for it. "The only ground for it is to be found in God Himself. God's love is altogether spontaneous." [75] And it is "unmotivated" in that there is nothing in man that can motivate it; it has no motive outside itself, in the personal worth of man. Human love is motivated; God's love is spontaneous and "unmotivated".

    2. Agape is "indifferent to value". By this Nygren means that Agape does not consider the value of its object. When Jesus says that God loves the sinner, it does not mean that the sinner is "better" than the righteous. That God, the Holy One, loves the sinner, cannot be because of his sin, but in spite of his sin. Neither does God love the righteous because they are "better". Nygren says, "It is only when all thought of worthiness of the object is abandoned that we can understand what Agape is." [77] There is no limit on God's love; the distinction between the worthy and unworthy, the righteous and sinner, set no bounds on God's love. "He makes His sun to rise on the evil and the good, and sends rain on the just and the unjust" (Matt. 5:45).

    3. Agape is creative. "Agape does not recognize value, but creates it. Agape loves, and imparts value by loving." [78] Nygren considers this to be deepest and ultimately decisive feature of the Christian idea of love. This is the feature that is very much obscured in modern theology. Since Ritschl's time it has been common for theologians to speak of "the infinite value of the human soul" as one of central ideas of Christianity, and to connect it to the "Fatherhood of God". Nygren says that this is by no means a central idea of Christianity. Only a false exegesis has made it possible to find support for it in the Scriptures. This has a destructive influence on the understanding the nature of God's love. The suggestion that man by nature possesses such an unalienable value easy gives rise to the thought that it is this infinite worth on which God sets his love. Even though this Divine spark may seem to have been quenched in a man sunk in sin, it is none the less present, awaiting it being awakened and actualizing. Viewed in this light, God's forgiveness of sins means merely that He disregards the manifold faults and failings and looks at the imperishable value which not even sin can destroy. This interpretation of Divine forgiveness misunderstands forgiveness and love. When Jesus says, "Thy sins are forgiven thee", he is not recognizing an already existing value which justifies overlooking of faults, but is the bestowal of a gift. Something new is added, something really new is taking place. The forgiveness of sin is a creative work of Divine power which changes the individual.

    4. Agape is the initator of fellowship with God. This is the new thing that has taken place in Divine forgiveness; a new relationship to God has been created. Fellowship with God is not ebstablished from man's side by any meritorious conduct, or even by repentance and admendment. There is no way at all from man's side that leads to God. God Himself in His love has provided the way to Himself and that way is through His Son whom God in His love sent. There is no way for man to come to God, but only the way for God to come to man; the way that God's love provides.

    Nygren summarises and concludes his account of these two fundamental motifs and their contrary tendencies in the following table. [210]
    Eros is acquisitive and longing. Agape is sacrifical giving.
    Eros is an upward movement. Agape comes down.
    Eros is man's way to God. Agape is God's way to man.
    Eros is man's effort:
    it assumes that man's salvation is his work.
    Agape is God's grace;
    salvation is the work of Divine love.
    Eros is egocentric love,
    a form of self-assertion of the highest,
    noblest, sublimest kind.
    Agape is unselfish love,
    it "seeketh not its own",
    it gives itself away.
    Eros seeks to gain its life,
    a life divine, immortalised.
    Agape lives the life of God,
    therefore dares to "lose it."
    Eros is the will to get and
    possess which depends on want and need.
    Agape is freedom in giving,
    which depends on wealth and plenty.
    Eros is primarily man's love;
    God is the object of Eros.
    Even when it is attributed to God,
    Eros is patterned on human love.
    Agape is primarily God's love;
    "God is Agape".
    Even when it is attributed to man,
    Agape is patterned on Divine love.
    Eros is determined by the quality,
    the beauty and worth, of its object;

    it is not spontaneous,
    but "evoked", "motivated".
    Agape is sovereign in relation to its object,
    and is directed to both
    "the evil and the good";
    it is spontaneous,
    "overflowing", "unmotivated".
    Eros recognises value in its object -
    and loves it.
    Agape loves -
    and creates value in its object.

    Love expresses a relation between a subject who loves and an object that is loved. If the study of this relation focuses on the personal objects of this love, there are four different forms of love. There is (1) God's love for man, (2) man's love for God, (3) man's love for his fellow-men, and (4) man's love for himself. In this last form the subject and the object of the relation coincide; this does not mean that this form of love is not a relation, for there are other relations that have this characteristic: the equality relation in mathematics has this characteristic, called the reflextive property: A = A. When Nygren interprets these four forms in terms of Eros and Agape, he makes the following comparison between them. [211-217]

    1. When considering God's love for man in terms of Eros, it is impossible to speak of God's love for man, and God's love as Eros has no meaning. Eros is yearning desire; but God has no want or need, and therefore no desire nor striving. Eros is the way upward; but there is no way upward for God; God cannot ascend higher. And since Eros seeks the highest good, it is impossible for God to love man, because that would imply God loving something less than His own Divine perfection, which is the highest good. But when considering God's love for man in terms of Agape, this is the supreme act of God's love. Since Agape is the way down and every way is down from God, God's Agape can descend to man. And since Agape flows out of plenty and wealth, God can freely out of the riches of His Agape give to man what he needs. God's love as Agape is expressed in His love for man.

    2. When considering man's love for God in terms of Eros, Nygren has no difficulty in finding a place for man's love toward God. As Eros man's love reaches up toward God and seeks participation in the riches and blessedness of God. Here the upward striving of Eros comes into its own; human want and need seeks for satisfaction in the Divine fulness. Since Eros is acqisitive desire, striving to obtain advantages, and since God is the highest good, it is natural that man is attracted to God Himself with all desire and love. But since it is possible for man to love other things than the Divine, because of his distant from the Divine, Eros may be misdirected. But this does detract from Eros, but shows that man's love may be detracted from the higher to the lower, cheating man himself of the highest satisfaction. But when considering man's love toward God in terms of Agape, Nygren encounters a problem [213]. Agape is spontaneous and unmotivated love. But in his relation to God man's love can never be spontaneous and unmotivated. Man's love for God is awaken by God's love for him and is a response to His love. Thus man's love for God is caused by God's love and is motivated by God's love. Hence man's love for God may be spoken of in terms of Agape only in metaphorical sense. Furthermore, man loves God, not because on comparing Him with other things he finds Him more satisfying than anything else, but because God's unmotivated love has overwhelmed and taken control of him, so the he cannot do other than love God. Herein lies the profound meaning of the idea of predestination: "man has not selected God, but God has elected man." [214]

    3. When considering man's love for his heighbor in terms of Eros, love does not seek the neighbor for himself, but seeks him only in so far as it can utilize him as a means for its own ascent to the highest good. It is not man as such, but "God in man", that is loved. It is only with difficulty that a place can be found in Eros-love for man's love for his neighbor. But when speaking of man's love for his neighbor, love bears the stamp of Agape. Man's love for one's neighbor is similar to God's love for man. But when it is ask what is the grounds for such love, and a reason for that love is looked for, then the love for one's neighbor is transformed into Eros-love. Unless man's love for his neighbor is directed to the neighbor alone, apart from any ulterior motive, unless it is concerned exclusively with him and no other end in view, this love of neighbor is not Agape. When it said that Christian neighborly love is "for God's sake", it is not speaking of God as the end, but of God as the cause of that love. God is not the ultimate end, the ultimate object of the love, but He is the starting-point and the energizer of that love. Thus the phrase "for God's sake" does not have a teleological but only a causal meaning. Everyone who has been gripped and mastered by God's love cannot but pass on this love to his neighbor.

    4. Finnally when considering man's love for himself in terms of Eros, this self-love is what Eros is essentially is. But Agape recognises no kind of self-love, and excludes self-love entirely from consideration. In this form Agape is the direct opposite of self-love.

    When Nygren [219] arranges these various forms of love in the order of their importance for Agape and to Eros respectively, giving a rating of 3 to the form which in each case it dominates the conception of love as a whole, and a rating of zero to any form in which is completely absent from it, he gets the the following table.
    Agape
    Eros
    3 God's love 0
    2 Neighborly love 1
    1 Love for God 2
    0 Self-love 3

    Evaluation of Nygren's View of Agape.
    As commendable as this work of Nygren is, there are some difficulities with his understanding of Agape. His historical treatment and analysis of Eros is thorough and accurate. But his analysis of Agape is greatly influence by this treatement of Eros. He tends to define Agape purely as the negation of Eros. This may be seen in his definition of Agape as spontaneous and "unmotivated". By spontaneous he means uncaused and by unmotivated he means not motivated by anything of value in its object. His second characteristic confirm this negative definition of Agape: Agape is "indifferent to value". As Nygren says,

    "This does not add anything new to what has already been said; but in order to prevent a possible misunderstanding, it is necessary to give special emphasis to one aspect of the point we have just made. ... It is only when all thought of the worthiness of the object is abandoned that we can understand what Agape is." [77]
    This negative treatment is partly counteracted by his discussion of the other two characteristics of Agape: "Agape is creative" and "Agape is the initiator of fellowship with God". But these play little part in his treatment of the history of Agape and they do not define Nygren's concept of Agape. The nearest that Nygren comes to a positive definition of Agape is his contrast between Eros and Agape: Eros is egocentric love and Agape is theocentric love. [209]

    But not only does Nygren not positively define Agape, but his treatment of it as unselfish love, as the negation of Eros, makes it difficult for him to interpret certain passages of Scripture, especially the commandment to love one's neighbor as oneself (Matt. 22:34-40; Mark 12:28-34). Nygren rejects the interpretation of this command that there is commandment of self-love in this commandment to love one's neighbor. He also rejects the interpretation that love of self is being approved of. Nygren says,

    "Self-love is man's natural condition, and also the reason for the perversity of his will. Everyone knows how by nature he loves himself. So, says the commandment of love, thou shalt love thy neighbour. When love receives this new direction, when it is turned away from one's self and directed to one's neighbour, then the natural perversion of the will is overcome. So far is neighbourly love from including self-love that it actually excludes and overcomes it." [101]
    Nygren here misunderstands the command to love one's neighbor as one's self. This is not what the commandment says; it does not reject, exclude and overcome self-love. It does not oppose love of neighbor to love of self. This interpretation is the reading of Nygren's own theology into this commandment; according to his theology the essence of sin is self-love and thus it must be rejected, excluded and overcome. This commandment of neighborly love neither approves or disapproves of self-love, but only refers to self-love as a fact of human existence that can provide a criterion by which the love of neighbor may be measured; as you love yourself, love your neighbor. As one in love of self would not kill one's self, then do not kill your neighbor, etc.

    Nygren's Agape motif is a distortion of the Biblical Agape. By defining Agape as "spontaneous and unmotivated" in contrast to Eros which is caused and motivated by it object, Nygren has misunderstood Biblical Agape. Biblical Agape is not a thing but a personal relationship between persons, between a subject (the person who loves, the lover) and an object (the person loved). Neither is Agape a desire like Eros, but a relation that is established by the decision of the person loving. Thus Agape is not caused by a desire for the object loved. But Agape is not "uncaused", "spontaneous", but there is a reason for the decision, for the choice to love. Agape is not uncaused, but is "caused", but not by its object. Why love? Nygren says that there is no motivation for Agape. But Nygren is wrong. Agape is not unmotivated; it is motivated but it is not motivated by its object; Agape is motivated by someone other than its object; by being loved the one loving is motivated to love. Nygren's analysis of Agape as spontaneous and unmotivated, depersonalized it and reducess it to a thing. Agape is
    (1) a personal relationship, a relation between persons;
    (2) Agape is a choice of the person loving; and
    (3) the object of Agape is not a thing, an "it", but a person, a "thou", "you".

    Nygren's distortion of the Biblical Agape is seen most clearly in his treatment of Agape in the writings of John [146-159]. He considers the Johannine treatment of Agape as weakening the idea of Agape in the writings of Paul. According to Nygren, John weakens the idea of Agape by his "Agape-metaphysic," his "particularism", and his uncertain position between unmotivated and motivated love, the modification of love in the direction of acquisitive love. [151] All these contributed, according to Nygren, in their various ways to this weakening of the Agape motif. According to Nygren, "the Johannine conception of love represents in a measure the transition to a stage when the Christian idea of love is no longer determined soley by the Agape motif, but by 'Eros and Agape'." [158]

    Nygren finds in the writings of John a "duality" in the Johannine idea of Agape [151]; Nygren finds this duality in three areas:

    1. in the area of Johannine "metaphysics of Agape" and its relation to spontaneous, unmotivated love;
    2. in the area of Johannine particularism of Christian love for "the brethern" and the universalism of the commands to "love your neighbor" and "to love your enemies";
    3. in the area of the problem of love for God and love of the world.

    1. Nygren claims that John goes beyond Paul in the tendency to trace love back to God's love by claiming that God is love. Nygren interpretes John's statement that "God is love" (I John 4:8, 16) to mean that "love is one with the substance of God" [151]; that "God is in His very 'essence' Agape" [153]; and that "love, Agape, is God" [147]. This "identity of God and Agape" is called by Nygren the "metaphysic of Agape", and Nygren claims that it threatens the spontaneous and unmotivated nature of Agape that he thinks he had found in Paul's writings. But Nygren has misunderstood Agape in Paul's writings. In fact he ignores the Paul's definition of Agape in Rom. 13:10: "Love works no evil to its neighbor", that is, love does good to its neighbor. Nygren quotes this passage but only to assert Paul's statement in last part of the verse: "Therefore, love is the fulfilling of the law." [127] Nygren by defining Agape as spontaneous and unmotivated he has not only misunderstood Agape in Paul's writings but he has also misinterpreted John's statement that "God is love". John's statement is not asserting that God is identical to Agape, that God and Agape are identical. The "is" here in this verse does not assert an identity between God and Agape, but a characteristic of God. It is describing what God is in Himself, in that the three persons of the Trinity love each other; the Father loves the Son, etc. (John 3:35; 5:20; 15:9-10; 17:23-24, 26). And it is also describing what God is in His relation to us, His creation, the world. "God so love the world that gave His only Son..." (John 3:16). John is making explicit what is implicit in Paul's statements about God's love:
      "But God shows his love for us in that
      while we were yet sinners Christ died for us." (Rom. 5:8)
      "In this the love of God was made manifest among us,
      that God sent his only Son into the world,
      so that we might live through him." (I John 4:9)
      John does not "take us a stage further by his identification of God and Agape" [149], but is expressing those aspects of God's love that Paul did not have occasion to express. In fact, Paul stresses those aspects of God's love that are related to his personal experience of conversion from a persecutor of the church. There is no developement in idea of Agape from Paul's theology to John's theology. Neither Paul nor John understands Agape as spontaneous and unmotivated and the Johannine idea of Agape does not occupy "a somewhat uncertain position between unmotivated and motivated love". [152]

    2. There is no duality in the Johannine idea of man's love. And John does not restrict love for neighbor to love for brethern. Love of the brethern does not mean love for one's neighbor is excluded and the universal, unlimited love of one's enemy is now limited and particularised to love of brethern. Nygren claims,
      "That which from one point of view represents an enhancement of the idea of Agape appears from another point of view to constitute a danger to it. Just because love in John is limited to narrower circle of 'the brethern', it is able to develop a far greater warmth and intimacy than it otherwise could; but this limitation involves for Christian love the risk of losing its original unmotivated character, and of being restricted to the brethren to the exclusion of outsiders and enemies." [154]
      Nygren's assessment of the Johannine treatment of the love of the brethern is wrong. God's love produces a fellowship of love; the love for the brethern for one another is its mark and reflects the pattern of the mutual love of the Father and the Son. Just as the Father loves the Son, and the Son loves his own, his disciples, so they "the brethern" are to love each other. Jesus prays, "That they may be one, even as we are one." (John 17:11, 22-23). Nygren sees in this love of the brethren for one another a threat to the original unmotivated character of Agape, as love for one's enemies; they now love the brethern "because" they are brethern, and hence love for the outsider is excluded. Here Nygren misunderstanding of Agape as unmotivated leads him to find a difference where is no difference. If the brethern love each other as they were loved when they not brethern, where is the problem? Jesus and John were not proposing a different kind of love for the brethern and love for one's enemies. Jesus said to his disciples, "This is my commandment, that you love one another as I have loved you" (John 15:12). And this is same love he had for them as sinners.

    3. Nygren's misunderstanding of Agape is shown in his interpretation of the Johannine exhortation not to love the world. "Love not the world, neither the things that are in the world. If any man love the world, the love of the Father is not him" (I John 2:15). Nygren sees here a change of meanning of love.
      "When we are warned against love of the world, it is obviously cannot be generous, self-giving Agape-love that is meant, but only 'the love of desire', or acquisitive love. Only to the latter sense can 'love of the world' be set in opposition to love of God; though when it is, there is always the risk that even love for God will be understood as acquisitive love." [157]
      Here Nygren's misunderstanding of Agape is obvious. Neither is the love of the world or the love for the Father "self-giving Agape-love" nor are they acquisitive love. In both cases, love is the love for them as the Good; a wrong love of the world as the Good, and a right love of God as the Good. "And Jesus said to him, 'Why do you call me good? No one is good but God alone.'" (Mark 10:18). Agape is not entirely independent of the value of its object. How Agape acts for the good of its object is determined by the value assigned to it by the one loving. How God in His love acts for the good of object of His love is determined by the value He assigns to it. Its value is not determined by its object inherent value, but by the value God assigns to it. The idea that Agape is value indifferent is only partially true. Agape is not caused by the inherent value of the object but it is caused by the value that lover chooses to give to it. It is obvious that the love of God as well as the love of the world is determined by the value that the lover assigns to them. But the love of God and the love of the world are mutually exclusive; man cannot love both God and the world, because God and world are not both the Good. Only God is the Good, and to love the world is to treat it as the Good, as God; and this would be the sin of idolatry. "If any man love the world, the love of the Father is not him" (I John 2:15).

    ENDNOTES

    [1] All page references to Nygren's book Agape and Eros is shown within a pair of brackets [] in this document.
    Anders Nygren, Agape and Eros,
    Part I: A Study of the Christian Idea of Love,
    Part II: The History of the Christian Ideas of Love.
    Translated by Philip S. Watson.
    (New York and Evanston: Harper & Row, Publishers, 1969)
    This book was first published in England by the S.P.C.K. House:
    Part I in 1932; part II, Vol. I in 1938;
    Part II, Vol. II in 1939;
    revised, in part retranslated, and published in one volume in 1953.
    The first paperback edition was published in 1969 by arrangement with the Westminster Press, publishers of the United States edition.