The inner relationship of these fields of knowledge can be seen
by examining the role that intuition plays in the production of
knowledge. Intuition has two principal roles:
(1) We intuit the particulars of sense directly. And from sense
particulars we form definitions, and make inductions, providing
the premises for deductions.
(2) At the other pole of our experience we also intuit the most
general principles of explanation, including logical principles themselves.
And between these two poles the basic structuring of theories goes on.
Theories involve definitions, axioms, postulates, and hypotheses.
Axioms are the indemonstrable primary premises of demonstration,
that is, notions commonly held to be true;
postulates relate to the subject whose attributes are to be
examined. According to Aristotle, unlike axioms, postulates are demonstrable,
but are used in a given inquiry without demonstration.
Hypotheses are like postulates in that they are capable of proof,
but are accepted for the purpose of the examination without proof.
They differ from postulates in ranging more widely, and including
more than the primary premises of the demonstration.
Modern mathematics and logic do not recognize Aristotle's distinction
between axioms and postulates, treating postulates as equivalent to axioms,
as the assumed without proof premises of demonstration.
Aristotle believed in real definitions; that is, definitions are either true, or not true, of the thing defined. And a true definition expresses the essence of the thing defined. To do so, it is necessary to relate the term being defined to the larger class of which it is a member, that is, its genus, and at the same time one must state how the sub-class of the thing being defined (the species) differs from other members of the genus class. When "man" is defined as a "rational animal," this is a definition by genus and difference, the genus being "animal" and the differentia being "rationality." The definition of man gives the essence of species man as a "rational animal."
This description of definition uses three of the five predicables: species, genius, and difference. A predicable (from the Latin praedicare "to affirm") is a type of predicate that may be affirmed or denied of something. The other two predicables are "property" and "accident." While the definition of a thing is expected to state the essence of the thing, a "property," while not stating its essence, yet it does belongs only to that thing. For example, to be capable of learning grammar is a property, and yet this capacity is not part of the definition of "man." An "accident," on the other hand, is a predicate with only a contingent relation to its subject. It just happens to characterize the subject in question. The red color of red house is an accident in that the house might have been some other color, and might be another color tomorrow. Aristotle did not identify "species" as a predicable, although the concept entered into his discussion and his list of predicables is: definition, genus, differentia, property, and accident.
When we make inductions from the particulars of sense, we get generalizations and abstractions. Aristotle was confident that intuition, or direct seeing, gives the nature of what is sensed before him. In the comparison of any sense data, one can generalize about their nature, seeing what they have in common, and how they differ. In On Memory and Recollection (Ch. II, par. 611), Aristotle advanced the associative principles of similarity, contrast, and contiguity to apply to this process. Induction separates or abstracts the sense datum from some of the conditions of its existence in the world making generalization possible. When induction is done correctly, we are both thinking the form in, and abstracting the form from, the images or phantasmata of sense. Logic represents a higher level of abstraction, an abstraction of the universal essence from the particular existence of things in the world.
According to Aristotle, science, in the strict sense of the word, is "demonstrated knowledge of the causes of things." Such demonstrated knowledge is obtained by syllogistic deduction from premises that in themselves are true. Thus in Aristotle's view, science is a matter of syllogistic demonstrations from certain or true premises. Therefore, at the center of Aristotle's logic is the syllogism, that is, that form of reasoning whereby, given two propositions called the premises, a third proposition called the conclusion follows necessarily from them. Aristotle was the first philosopher to formulate the theory of the syllogism, and his minute analysis of its various forms was definitive, so far as subject-predicate propositions are concerned; so that to this part of deductive logic little has been added since his day. According to Aristotle, logic is the science of predicating properties of subjects and deductively drawing conclusions from them as premises by means of the syllogism. The basis of syllogistic reasoning is the presence of a term common to both premises (the middle term) so related as subject or predicate of each of the other terms of the premises that a conclusion may be drawn regarding the relation of these terms to one another. Since this syllogistic reasoning depends upon the "middle term," Aristotle believed that the advance of knowledge depended upon the discovery of "middle terms."
Aristotle gave clear expression to two of the three Laws of Thought. He says of the principle of contradiction: "The firmest of all principles is that it is impossible for the same thing to belong and not to belong to the same thing at the same time in the same respect." And of the principle of the excluded middle he says: "It is not possible that there should be anything between the two parts of a contradiction, but it is necessary either to affirm or deny one thing of any one thing." Aristotle nowhere states the principle of identity, although it is presupposed.
Aristotle also recognized the modality of propositions, that is, the alternate ways of classifying propositions with respect to their relations to existence. Today there are three widely recognized modes; they are the modes of possibility, actuality, and necessity. If we let "p" stand for any proposition, the mode of possibility is expressed by "It is possible that p is true." The mode of actuality expressed simply by "p is true." And the mode of necessity is expressed by "It is necessary that p is true." These propositions and their negations, the impossible, not actual, and not necessary, are the modal propositions. Aristotle speaks of four modes of propositions: those which are possible, impossible, contingent, and necessary. The contingent modality speaks of that which may or may not be actual. Hence, the mode of contingency presupposes the modality of the possible. The necessary, in turn, has the modality of both the possible and the actual within it.
Aristotle also held that when one's premise are not certain but only probable, a shift from science to dialectic has occurred. There is also a further shift to eristic where one's goal is not knowledge but merely victory in disputation.
Chrysippus also contributed to definitions of modality. According to Cicero, Chrysippus followed Philo of Megara's definition of the possible as the self-consistent. According to Diogenes Laertius, Chrysippus defined the possible as that which will be true when external circumstances don't prevent its being so, and the necessary as that which is true, and cannot become false either in itself or through external circumstances.
The negative way, which is the method of exclusion from God of the imperfections of creatures, is pursued in his Mystical Theology (De mystica Theologia). The Pseudo-Dionysius preferred the negative way. As God is utterly transcendent, we praise Him best "by denying or removing all things that are - just as men who, carving a statue out of marble, remove all the impediments that hinder the clear perception of the latent image and by this mere removal display the hidden statue itself in its hidden beauty". Human beings are inclined to form anthropomorphic concepts of God, and it is necessary to strip away these human, all-too-human conceptions by the via remotionis. But the Pseudo-Dionysius does not mean that from this process there results a clear view of what God is in Himself: the analogy of the statue making must not mislead us. When the mind has stripped away from its idea of God the human modes of thought, it enters into the "Darkness of Unknowing", wherein it "renounces all the apprehension of the understanding and is wrapped in that which is wholly intangible and invisible... united ... to Him that is wholly unknowable"; this is mysticism. This "Darkness of Unknowing" is not due to the unintelligibility of the Object considered in itself, but to the finiteness of the human mind, which is blinded by excess of light. This doctrine is doubtless influenced by neo-Platonism.
In the same century, Peter of Spain (1226-1277), later Pope John XXI (1276), composed his Summulae Logicales, a logic textbook widely used in the later Middle Ages and up to the 17th century, passing through 150 printed editions. The point of view is very similar to that of William of Sherwood.