"We may regard the present state of universe as the effect of its past and the cause of its future. An intellect which at any given moment knew all the forces that aninate nature and the mutual positions of the beings that compose it, if this intellect were vast enough to submit the data to analysis, could condense into a single formula the movement of the greatest bodies of the universe and that of the lightest atom: for such an intellect nothing could be uncertain; and the future like the past would be present before its eyes."That is, an omniscient mind knowing the state of the universe at any instant could, by applying the laws of mathematics and physics, recreate the past and predict the future. The destiny of everything is established with a certainty as sure as two times two is four. Mathematics describes this destiny, for everything in the universe is determined by number, motion, and force. In a mechanized, determined world there is no ends or purposes; everything just goes on existing. Ideas, volitions, and actions are the necessary effect of matter acting on matter. The human will is determined by external physical and physiological causes. There is no free will; it is a meaningless conjunction of words. The will is bound fast in the fetters of matter in motion. Chance is also nothing but a word invented to express the known effect of an unknown cause. This is a very disturbing conclusion that even the materialist tried to modifiy its severity. Some said that man's actions, not his thoughts, were determined. This dualism is not very satisfactory; it makes thinking useless because it can not determine one's action; man remains an automaton. Others reinterpreted the meaning of freedom, in order retain some semblance of it; Voltaire wrote, "To be free means to be able to do what we like, not to be able to will what we like."
The problem of personal identity, or psychical substance, is in exactly the same case. Experience reveals us to be a succession of impressions, ideas, and emotions, memories and anticipations; and one does not experience a unifying framework for this succession. It is memory which leads us to believe in our identity through time; but memory lapses with consciousness. Consistent with these uncertainties, liberty is defined as action in keeping with our desires or wishes, in contrast to constraint, and not essentially opposed to the idea of necessity.
Indeterminism denies that everything has a cause. The indeterminist is a person who denies the Causal Principle in one or another of its forms. But no matter what version he takes, he is at disadvantage from the start; he cannot point at any causeless event, but only point at events for which no cause has been found. With regard to these, the indeterminist can reply, "Not all of them are determined. For many events we have found determining causes, but not for all; may it not be that the reason for this is that they (some of them, at any rate) have no causes? If you can't find gold, this may be because it escape your scrutiny, or it may be also because there is none to be found."
This is the conclusion that some indeterminist have drawn from the scientific developments in the science of quantum wave mechanics such as Heisenberg's "Principle of Indeterminancy," that indeterminism holds even there. As to events in the higher inorganic physical realm, the indeterminist is likely to leave these to the determinist. He says, "Maybe the path of projectiles and planets is determined, but with events on a higher level it is otherwise. This is particularly true of human behavior. There is surely no conclusive evidence for determinism in the realm of human actions. We have never found any exceptionless generalizations about human actions, and those that have been formulated are so vague and general that almost any kind of behavior could occur without falsifying them. Human behavior is predictable to only a very small degree. The 99.99 percent that we can't predict may, as the determinist says, be due to the complexity of the causes, but it may also due to a genuine indeterminism in human beings themselves. If this is true, then even a complete knowledge of the causal factors influencing a person would not enable us to predict whether, in a situation of choice, he would choose A or B. That decision remains free."
One might object that if there is no conclusive evidence for determinism in the realm of human actions, neither is there evidence against it. Then why does the indeterminist continue to reject the determinism? The chief motive underlying this rejection, in almost every case, is the belief that human beings have freedom of choice -- "free will" is the usual term for it -- and that if determinism were true, then they would not have freedom. Not all human actions are free, of course, but (according to the indeterminist) some are. If you are faced with a difficult moral choice, between two alternatives, A and B, then morality makes no sense unless you are really free to choose between them. Freedom of choice is the most precious of human possessions. Determinism, if it were true, would make freedom impossible. Determinism, therefore, is false, for free-will does exist.
From this point of view, no man is an atheist in the basic meaning of that word (that is, no god). Every man must have a god. Man is a religious animal who must necessarily have some object of ultimate allegiance and trust which functions as his guide of truth and his norm of conduct. Every man must choose a god. Though free to adopt the god of his choice, no man is free to avoid this decision. Every attempt to do so turns out to be not a denial of having a god but an exchange of gods. Every man must choose and have a god. To ask whether one believes in the existence of God is to completely misunderstand the issue. The issue is not whether one should choose between theism or atheism, that is, to believe in the existence of God or not, but whether one should choose this god or that god as the true God. Atheism wants you to believe in his god and his god is that God does not exist.
Since everyone must have a god, the crucial question for every man is:
Which god is the true God?
Or to put the question differently:
How are we to distinguish between the one true God, on the one hand,
and the many false gods on the other?
In other words, by what means can we determine
which of all possible gods are pretenders and which is the true one?
The clue to the answer to these
questions may be found in a further analysis of freedom.
As we have already seen, every man by the structure of his freedom
must have a god. That is, in every one of his choices a person must
necessarily appeal to some criterion by reference to which the
decision is made. And the ultimate criterion by which a person
makes his choices is his god. Clearly then the choice of one's god
is the most basic and fundamental choice that a man can make,
it lies behind and is presupposed by every other decision as to what
a man will do or think; it is clearly the most important exercise
of his freedom.
What should one choose as his ultimate criterion of decision?
Negatively, he should not choose that as his ultimate criterion
which will deny, destroy or limit the very freedom of
choice by which it is chosen.
And positively, he should choose that ultimate criterion
which will enhance and fulfil that freedom.
Any ultimate criterion that denies or takes away the very freedom
of choice by which it is chosen cannot be the true God. The choice
of such an ultimate criterion is a contradiction of man's basic
freedom of choice; such a god is fatal to man's freedom.
By freedom, we do not mean purposeless caprice or chance, indeterminism, but rather the ability of choice, freedom of will and decision, self-determination. Neither is this freedom an abstract entity, "freedom-in-general," Freiheit, but rather the concrete decision of someone, of a free agent. The most appropriate word for such a being who has such freedom is the word "person." A person is a being that is self-determining, not determined, who has freedom, free will, the ability to choose. A person is to be distinguished from a non-person, a thing, an "it", a being that is determined, not self-determining, that has no freedom, no free will, no ability to choose.
A god that is a thing has less freedom than the person who chooses it as his god. Such a god does not have as much freedom as the one who chooses it to be his god. Now a god who does not have at least the freedom that man himself has cannot be the true God. It cannot do any more for them than they can do for themselves. Such a god is only the projection of the whims and fancies of its worshippers because it is in reality inferior to them. As a minimum criterion, therefore, a god can be recognized as a false god if it has less freedom than man himself. To choose such a god as one's ultimate criterion of choice would be a denial of one's freedom of choice and the worst kind of bondage. Thus having used his freedom to give this god his ultimate allegiance, the worshipper finds his freedom denied to the point of extinction and himself bound in a miserable slavery. As long as the false god remains his ultimate criterion of decision, he will not have the grounds for rejecting that god, since that god has not allowed him to have freedom of choice to do so. His power of choice having been effectively taken away from him, he is unable to reject the false god and free himself from its bondage. The commitment to such a god is the denial of human freedom. Therefore, a false god can also be recognized by the effect that it has upon the freedom of the one who gives it his allegiance; it limits the freedom and puts into bondage the one who chooses it as his god. The true God, on the other hand, sets free the one committed to him and fulfils and enhances his freedom. The true God must be at least a person in order to have at least as much freedom as the one who chooses Him as his god. But the true God must not only be a person, He must also have unlimited freedom if He is to be able to do the things He promises and to deliver the one who cries to Him in trouble and need. A god without unlimited freedom might not be able to keep his promises or to save the one who cries to him. Therefore, a god that does not have unlimited freedom must be a false god. The true God, on the other hand, has unlimited freedom; He can do whatever He pleases (Psa. 115:3; 135:6); He can save when He is called upon (Isa. 43:11; 45:15-17). The true God, therefore, is a person (or persons) with unlimited freedom.
It is this knowledge of what the true God must be like that lies behind all primitive religions, with their anthromorphic gods. Primitive man knows what a god must be like in order for it to be the true God. This knowledge derived intuitively from the nature of his freedom makes him uneasy about the things that he worships as god. He knows that the true God must be a living God. But having failed to encounter such a God, he fills the vacuum with what he imagines to be a facsimile of Him. And since the highest living being he knows is himself, he makes gods in his own image. He also knows that the true God must be a God of unlimited power, not limited like himself. He therefore identifies these anthropomorphic creations with the powerful forces that he sees in the physical world about him. Beyond the simple and profound suspicion that such a God does exist, he is at the end of his knowledge ("...whom ye ignorantly worship..." Acts 17:23 KJV).
In what way can man find any additional knowledge of the true God?
In the same way in which he gets knowledge about another person:
by what the other person says and does. But the
initiative lies with the other person. If he remains silent and
inactive, no knowledge is available in addition to the fact that he is
there. Therefore, if man is to know anything additional about the true
God, God must take the initiative and reveal Himself in word
and/or deed. And the true God has taken the initiative and has revealed
Himself in word and deed. The Bible is a record of the "words and
the mighty acts of God." The true God is not silent and He is not
inactive; He has spoken and He has acted. This is recorded for us
in a book, the Bible. And we know that these are the words and
deeds of the true God because they are the words and the acts of a
God who is a personal being and has unlimited freedom and power.
The God who is revealed in the Scriptures of the Old and New Testament
is the living God who created all things.
(The living God - Joshua 3:10; I Sam. 17:26; Psa. 84:2; Jer.
10:10; Matt. 16:16; Acts 14:15; I Thess. 1:9; I Tim. 3:15; Heb. 10:31;
The Creator - Gen. 1:1; 2:3-4; Ex. 4:11; Neh. 9:6; Job 38:4;
Psa. 90:2; 102:25; 104:1-5,24; Isa. 40:28; 44:24; 45:11-12,18;
48:12-12; Jer. 10:11-12; John 1:1-3; Acts 17:24; I Cor. 8:6; Col.
1:16; Heb. 1:2,10; 11:3; Rev. 4:11).
Because He is a person, He is alive; and because He has unlimited
freedom, He is the all powerful Creator of all things. The God
of the Bible is the true God, and all other gods are false.
The following are the "Five Points" of Calvinism:
Arminius rejected the Unconditional Election of the Five Points as unscriptural. He argued that God chooses those to be saved whom he foreknew would believe in Christ. According to Arminius election is conditional; God's choice is conditioned by His foreknowledge of whom will believe. Calvinists reject this Conditional Election arguing that God foreknows only what He has sovereignly willed to take place. They argued that everything that takes place including the choices of man was immutably determined and fixed by God in eternity, and that all that happens is nothing but what He had ordained to be before anything was created. God's foreknowledge then depends upon the purpose and plan of God and that God foreknows only what he has willed to take place. Arminians reject this determinism arguing that it leaves no place for man's free will which God gave to man when He created him, and also it makes God the cause of sin and evil in the world. The Calvinist attempt to counter this argument by replying that sin is caused directly by man and the evil in the world is caused by Satan and his fallen angels; God is therefore not responsible for sin and evil. God wills only the good, because His nature is good, not evil or sinful. "But," the Arminians asks, "where did the evil and sin come from? If God wills everything, then God must have willed the evil and sin." The Arminians argue that man and the angels must have free will and that sin and evil are caused by the wrong choices which they make by the exercise of their free wills. Thus sin and evil is not caused by God but by those beings that God has created with free will.
Arminius did not reject the Total Depravity or Total Inability of the Five Points. He believed profoundly in original sin, understanding that the will of natural fallen man is not only maimed and wounded, but that it is entirely unable, apart from prevenient grace, to do any good thing. He believed that by the fall man has lost his free will and his nature has become corrupt or sinful. Man is thus totally unable to do anything to merit salvation. His followers have not always agreed with him on this point, and have modified the doctrine of original sin to teach that man since the fall is partially unable to do any good thing. In order to allow for man's free will, they teach that man's sinful nature does not determine his choices, but is only a tendency to sin. The sinful nature only hinders man from doing the good.
Arminius also rejected the Limited Atonement of the Five Points as unscriptural. Christ's atonement is unlimited. He understood such scriptures that say "he died for all" (II Cor. 5:15; compare II Cor. 5:14; Titus 2:11; I John 2:2) to mean what they say. Some Calvinists, such as the Puritan John Owens, argue that the "all" means only all of those who have been elected to be saved. Arminius also rejected the Irresistible Grace of the Five Points, arguing that saving grace can be resisted and rejected. Since some men have resisted God's saving grace and rejected it, these men are lost and not saved. They are not saved because God did not choose them but because they did not choose God; they resisted and rejected the saving grace of God. Arminius also rejected the Perseverance of the Saints of the Five Points arguing that since the believer still has free will after conversion, he could reverse his decision of faith in Christ and reject Christ, and thus loose his salvation and be eternally lost.
The following are the "Five Points" of Arminianism:
Click HERE to read an evaluation of Calvinism and Arminianism.
But according to the Scriptures man does not sin because of a inherited sinful nature, but because of spiritual death received from Adam.
"12 Therefore, as through one manMan's nature is not sinful or good, but is what he choose it to be; if he chooses a false god as his ultimate criterion of his choices, his choices will be sinful. Since men are spiritually dead, that is, not spiritually alive in a personal relationship to God, they will choose a false god as their ultimate criterion of their choices of how they will think or act. God opposes man's basic sin of idolatry and the sins that follow from it; this opposition is the wrath of God. And if a man continues to serve his false god, refusing the gift of eternal life in Jesus Christ, he will receive eternal death, the wages of this slavemaster. This has nothing to do with merit or demerit, nor with the execution of justice in paying the penalty for law breaking. Romans 6:23 is about the slavery of sin and its consequences; the word "sin" in the singular there refers not to the sinful nature but to sin as a slavemaster, who pays the wages of eternal death. And this eternal death is not the penalty of sin, but is the wages paid by sin as a slavemaster.
sin entered into the world,
and death through sin,
and so death passed unto all men,
because of which all sinned: --
13 for until the law sin was in the world;
but sin is not reckoned when there is no law.
14 Nevertheless death reigned from Adam until Moses,
even over those who had not sinned
after the likeness of the transgression of Adam,
who is the type of him who was to come." (Rom. 5:12-14 ERS).
"The wages of sin is death,Sin as a slave master is the false god that a man chooses as his ultimate criterion of all his choices. Thus all men sin in choosing a false god and from this false god as their slavemaster they receive the wages of this slavemaster, eternal death. God does not choose just some to be saved, leaving the rest to be damned. But each man chooses his god and lord; if he chooses a false god that becomes his slavemaster, then he will receive the consequence of that choice, eternal death. But if he chooses to receive the true God as his God and His gift of eternal life in Jesus Christ, His Son, acknowledging Him as his Lord, he is saved. God has chosen to save all men, if they will receive that salvation. God has not chosen just a few to be saved, but all men. But not all men will be saved, not because God has not chosen them, but they have not chosen Him. Each man must make his own choice of which god he will have as his ultimate criterion of choice, to be his god and lord. God does not make that choice for him. In the preaching of the Gospel, the Holy Spirit opens the eyes of the spiritually blind and sets their wills free from the slavery of sin to their false god, so that they can choose the true God. Then if they refuse to choose the true God and to receive His gift of life, they are left in spiritual death and in their sin.
but the free gift of God is eternal life in Christ Jesus our Lord."
(Rom. 6:23).
The slavery of sin is not a sinful nature but the choices made in following a false god; it is not a determinism by one's nature but the self-determinism by one's personal choice according to one's false ultimate criterion. And salvation is not a determinism by God that overrides the determinism of the sinful nature. God's sovereignty in salvation is not a determinism but the setting of man free from the bondage of sin to a false god so that he is free to choose the true God. Biblical theology is not deterministic in either sense. Calvinism misinterprets God's sovereignty deterministically in such passages of Scripture as Rom. 8:29.
"Those whom he foreknew, he also foreordainedThe Greek verb here translated "foreknew," proginosko, means "to know beforehand." It is used in general to refer to knowledge that is previously had (Acts 26:5; II Pet. 3:17). The Greek verb is used only 5 times in New Testament, two times in the letter to the Romans; here in Rom. 8:29 about believers and in Rom. 11:2 about Israel. The fifth occurrence is in I Pet. 1:20 about Christ "having been foreknown before the foundations of the world." The Greek noun, prognosis, translated "foreknowledge," occurs twice in the New Testament, in Acts 2:23 about Christ and in I Pet. 1:2 about believers as the elect or chosen ones. Paul uses the verb here to refer to God's knowledge of believers before they knew God. It is equivalent to choosing beforehand someone as God did Israel (Rom. 11:2). It does not refer to the omniscience of God whereby God knows all things before they happen. Paul is here talking about God's personal knowledge and not His objective knowledge of all things. The Greek verb here translated "foreordained," proorizo, literally means "to set boundaries beforehand," hence, "to decide upon beforehand, to appoint, designate, and choose beforehand." It is used 6 times in the New Testament, twice in chapter 8 of Romans (in verses 29 and 30) twice in Ephesians 1 (in verses 5 and 11), Acts 4:28 and I Cor. 2:7. In none of these places does it mean a causal determinism that makes free will impossible. As Paul says in Eph. 1:11, God "works all things according to the counsel of his will." Although some theologians have interpreted these words as teaching such causal determinism, Paul's choice of words do not say that all things are causally determined by God. The translation of this Greek verb proorizo as "predistined" makes Paul seem to teach this determinism.
to be conformed to the image of his Son,
that he might be the firstborn among many brethren."
Calvinism is wrong in interpreting the slavery of sin as a determinism of the sinful nature and Arminianism is wrong in not taking the slavery of sin seriously in their stress on the freedom of the will. Neither of them recognize the Biblical truth that the basic sin is idolatry and that man sins in choosing a false god as his ultimate criterion of all his decisions because he is spiritually dead. They both distort the Biblical theology of salvation in their dispute about man's free will. Salvation is neither a monergism on God's part nor a monergism on man's part; it is the free gift by grace on God's side that is received through faith on man's side.
"8 For by grace you have been saved through faith;
and this is not of yourselves, it [salvation] is the gift of God;
9 not of works, lest anyone should boast."
(Eph. 2:8-9 ERS).
But the Scriptures do teach that Adam as the head of the human race brought spiritual and physical death on the whole human race (Rom. 5:12-19; I Cor. 15:21-22); but this was not a punishment for the sins of the human race, neither personally for their own sins nor as a participation in Adam's sin ( Rom. 5:13-14). Neither does the Scriptures teach that man inherited a corrupt or sinful nature from Adam. On the contrary, the Scriptures teaches that man inherited death, spiritual and physical, from Adam ( Rom. 5:12; I Cor. 15:21-22). And according to Rom. 5:12d ("because of which [death] all sinned" ERS) all men sin because of death ("the sting of death is sin", I Cor. 15:55-56). And this death is not the sinful nature. These are two totally different concepts. The sinful nature is the nature of man that is sinful and the nature of man is what man is - that which makes man what he is and what he does. The nature of anything is that essence of the thing that determines what it is and how it acts. The sinful nature is that nature of man, and because it is sinful, makes him sin. Death, on the other hand, is a negative relationship of separation. Physical death is the separation of man's spirit from his body, spiritual death is the separation of man's spirit from God, and eternal death ("the second death," Rev. 20:14) is the eternal separation of man from God. Spiritual death is the opposite of spiritual life, which is to know personally the true God and Jesus Christ whom He has sent (John 17:3). That is, spiritual death is not to know personally the true God and Jesus Christ whom He sent. Knowledge is a relationship between the knower and that which is known; it is not a nature nor the property of a nature. Now it should be clear that spiritual death is not the sinful nature; it is a negative relationship between man and God and not the nature of man.
Spiritual death is not the necessary cause but the ground or condition of sin, the choice of a false god. The Greek preposition epi translated "because" in the last clause of Rom. 5:12 means "on the condition of" or "on the basis of". It does not imply any necessary or deterministic causal connection between death and sin. Man sins by choice, not of necessity. In this state of spiritual death, he chooses freely his false god and thus sins. Then his false god puts him into bondage; he becomes a slave of sin, his false god being his slave master. The Calvinistic doctrine of Total Depravity or Total Inability misinterpretes this slavery of sin and equates it with the sinful nature or the results of the sinful nature, and turns the slavery of sin into a determinism and the denial of human freedom of choice.
31 Jesus then said to the Jews who had believed in him,These words of Jesus clearly identifies freedom as freedom from sin, and sin as a slavery. This freedom comes about through the knowledge of the truth. And the truth is the Son of God. As Jesus tells his disciples later, "I am ... the truth,...".
"If you continue in my word, you shall truly be my disciples,
32 and you will know the truth,
and the truth will make you free."
33 They answered him,
"We are descendants of Abraham,
and have never been in bondage to anyone.
How is it that you say,
'You will be made free'?"
34 Jesus answered them,
"Truly, truly, I say to you,
every one who commits sin is a slave to sin.
35 The slave does not continue in the house forever.
36 So if the Son makes you free,
you will be free indeed." (John 8:31-36)
5 Thomas said to him [Jesus],
"Lord, we do not know where you are going;
how can we know the way?"
6 Jesus said to him,
"I am the way, and the truth, and the life;
no one comes to the Father, but by me.
7 If you had known me,
you would have known the Father also;
henceforth you know him and have seen him."
(John 14:5-7)
What is truth?
In the history of philosophy, there have been two main theories
of the nature of truth: the correspondence and the coherence theory.
Both these theories of the nature of truth are theories of
propositional truth. That is, truth is a property of
propositions or statements. Both theories attempt to say how a
proposition may be true.
In the examination of these theories of propositional truth, we see that there is an another kind of truth: ontologial truth. The problem of propositional truth raises the problem of ontologial truth, the problem of the criterion of reality: how do we decide what is real? Thus the choice of the criterion of propositional truth leads to and involves the choice of something as real. That is, the truth of propositions are based on the reality of something that is the criterion of reality, ontological truth. Further more, each epistemology makes an ontological assertion as to what is real. Empiricism asserts the reality of the object (Realism) that is known through the senses. Rationalism asserts the reality of the rational (Idealism). Empiricism appeals to the reality of the object beyond the senses to establish the truths of the senses. Rationalism appeals to the reality of the rational, the universal and necessary, to establish the truths of reason. For both of these criteria of knowledge involves an appeal to something that is assumed to be real.
This raises the question: what is real? To answer this question an appeal must be made to a criterion of reality, the Truth. Thus the problem of the criterion of truth raises and involves the problem of ontological truth: what is the criterion of reality? The criterion of reality answers the question: what is real? Whatever is the criterion of reality is the Truth and the Truth is the criterion of reality; it is ultimate reality, the really real. Realism asserts that the objects of senses are ultimately real, the Truth; Idealism asserts that mind or the rational is the ultimately real, the Truth.
The analysis of the problem of ontological truth shows that both empiricism and rationalism make an appeal to a criterion of reality, the Truth, as the criterion of propositional truth: empiricism to the reality of the objects of sense knowledge, and rationalism to the rational, the universal and necessary.
But both empiricism and rationalism ignore the freedom of human choice in determining the criterion of knowledge of the truth. The criterion of knowledge is not rationally necessary nor empirically given; it is chosen. Both of these epistemologies allow no place for this choice.
Now an analysis of human choice discloses the fact that choice
involves a reference to a criterion of choice and ultimately to
an ultimate criterion of choice. The choice of what statements or
propositions are held to be true depends ultimately on the choice of
this ultimate criterion. This observation raises the question:
what is the ultimate criterion choice?
Since an impersonal or non-personal reality (Nature or Reason)
does not have this freedom, only another person who has the
freedom of choice can be this ultimate criterion. But not only
must this person have freedom of choice but he must be committed
to the preservation of freedom of the one who has chosen him,
that is, he must motivated by love. And in order to be able to
preserve that freedom, his freedom must be unlimited. This
implies that this person must also be the basis and ground of
the rest of reality; that is, he must be ultimate reality (God)
and the criterion of reality. And since the Truth is the criterion
of reality, that person will be the Truth. Thus the Truth is a person.
And if we are to know this person, that is, who he is and that
he exists, he must reveal himself. For the only way we can know
another person is only by what he says and does. But the
initiative lies with the other person. If he chooses to remain
silent and inactive, no knowledge can be had of him in addition
to the fact that he is there. If this person who is ultimate reality
(the Truth) is to be known, He must reveal Himself. The Bible claims
that He has taken the initiative and He has revealed Himself in word
and deed, and that the Bible is the record of that revelation.
Who is this person that is the Truth? The Biblical answer is that
Jesus Christ is the Truth. Jesus said,
"I am the way, the truth, and the life;
no man comes to the Father, except through me." (John 14:6).
He is the source of the knowledge of God. That is, Jesus
Christ, the Son of God, is the way to God, the revelation of God,
the Father, the Creator of all reality except God Himself.
Through Him, as the pre-incarnate Word of God, were all things made
and He is basis and ground of the rest of reality that God has created
(John 1:1-3; Col. 1:15-17). He is the criterion of the real,
the Truth, because through Him God has determined by His sovereign
creative choice what is real. And as such He is committed to the
preservation and fulfilment of our freedom.
"And you will know the truth and the truth will make you free...
So if the Son makes you free, you will be free indeed." (John 8:32, 36).
The Truth that will make you, a person, free is the person,
the Son of God. He sets free and perserves the freedom of one
who chooses Him as their ultimate criterion of the reality, as the Truth.
Click HERE to read the conclusion of the evaluation of Calvinism and Arminianism.