ROMANTICISM

  1. INTRODUCTION.
    Romanticism is a movement chiefly in European literature and the arts featuring an emphasis on imagination and emotion rather than reason and formal criteria. Beginning at the close of 18th century and reaching its peak in the early decades of of the 19th century, the movement was a revolt against the neo-Classicism of the late 17th and 18th century. The romantic writers seldom used the term themselves, and controversy has raged among critical and historical scholars of Western culture ever since as to its precise meaning and interpretation. Nevertheless, there are identifiable traits that distinguishes romanticism from earlier cultural periods, and most contemporary scholars, while disagreeing on details, recognize its descriptive validity. Certainly it characterizes a "temperament" (Crane Brinton) or personality, if not an epoch in cultural history as such. The term came from the Old French romanz (to write), which in the Middle Ages meant writing in the vernacular rather than in Latin. It gradually came to be applied to works of fiction and then to the untouched natural landscape. By the 18th century it referred to that which was sentimental, full of expression, and melancholly.

    The specific elements of romanticism are difficult to delineate because they exist in differing combinations in various writers and thinkers, depending upon their geograpical location, place in time, and personal connections. While acknowledging that there are exceptions, romanticism generally can be said to stress emotioinalism, sensualism, fantasy, and imagination over rational order and control. Reality is found not by rational thought but through feeling, immediate experience, spiritual illumination, brooding and listening to the inner voices. There is a subjectivism that emphasizes self-consciousness, the activity of the ego, introversion, and originality. A sense of mystery arises out of an inner longing for that which is unexperienced and unknown. Each personality should be allowed to unfold itself freely, according to its own genius, individual impulses, and idiosyncrasies. Romantics seek beauty, color, and adventure in out-of-the-way places and events and among the common people. The exotic is preferred over the familiar, rural life over that of the city. Prescribed unities and forms are rejected for that which is different, unconventional, novel, and spontaneous. Romantics have a deep interest in the past, especially the Middle Ages, as well as nonclassical (Nordic) mythology, folklore, and primitivism, and they contributed greatly to the recovering and publishing long-forgotten medieval historical records and literature. Finally, romantic art seems on the one hand to be sensuous, concrete, and down to the earth, yet simultaneosly it is much more visionary and even mystical. As Novalis put it, in the romantic view of life, "world becomes dream, dream becomes world."

  2. HISTORY OF ROMANTICISM.
    The movement arose in the 1790s as a reaction to the classicism and rationalism of the Enlightment, but elements of this revolt could be seen in earlier writers like Vico, Rousseau, James Thomson, and the Storm and Stress school in Germany (Klopstock, Herder, and the young Goethe and Schiller). Among the major romantic authors are Coleridge, Wordsworth, Byron, Shelley, Keats, Scott, and Blake in Britain, Madame de Stael, Musset, George Sand, and Victor Hugo in France; and Goethe, August and Friedrich von Schlegel, Novalis, Eichendorff, Kleist, Tieck, the Grimm brothers, and E. T. A. Hoffmann in Germany. There were also romantic music composers like Chopin, Schubert, and Schumann, painters like Delacroix and Turner, and philosophers like Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and Schopenhauer. The main romantic theologian was Schleiermacher. The movement had run its course by the end of 1830s, but some features continued even past midcentury.

    In philosophy, the movement marked a reaction against the 18th century Enlightment or Age of Reason. In a narrow sense, romanticism as a philosophical movement can be viewed as occuring during the initial phase of German absolute idealism, and as including the German philosophers Friedrich Schiller (1759-1805), Friedrich Von Schlegel (1772-1829), Johann Wolfgang Goethe (1749-1832), and Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768-1834).
    This does not mean that German idealism was the philosophy of romanticism. This interpretation of German idealism is open to serious objections.

    1. In the first place, it suggests the idea of a one way influence. That is to say, it suggests that the great idealist systems were simply the ideological expression of the romantic spirit, whereas in point of fact the philosophies of Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814) and Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775-1854) exercised a considerable influence on some of the romantics.
    2. In the second place, the leading idealist philosophers stood in somewhat different relations to the romantics. It can indeed be said that Schelling gave notable expression to the spirit of the romantic movement. But Fichte indulged in some sharp criticism of the romantics, even if the latter had derived inspiration from some of his ideas. And Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) had scant sympathy with some aspects of romanticism.
    3. In the third place, it is arguable that the term "philosophy of romanticism" would be better applied to the speculative ideas of Friedrich Schlegel and Novalis than to the great idealist systems.
    At the same time there was undoubtably some spiritual affinity between the idealist and romantic movements. The romantic spirit as such was indeed an attitude towards life and the universe rather than a systematic philosophy. And it is perfectly understandable that Hegel saw a considerable difference between systematic philosophical reflection and the utterances of the romantics. But when we look back on the German scene in the first part of 19th century, we are naturally struck by affinities as well as by differences. After all, metaphysical idealism and romanticism were more or less contemporary German cultural phenomena, and an undelying spiritual affinity is only what one expect to find.

    In a broader sense, the classification of romanticism as a philosophical movement might range back to the French philosopher Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) with his stress on nature, and forward to the German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860), and even Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900).

      .
    1. Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling.
      The German philosopher Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775-1854) was known as the philosopher of the Romantic movement and was friends with Goethe, Schiller, Novalis, Schlegel, and other luminaries of Romanticism. For a time he edited a journal with Hegel who was initially regarded as his disciple. Schelling was born in Leonberg, Wuttemberg, educated at Tubingen where Hegel and Holderlin were fellow students. He taught at Jena, Wurzburg, Munich, Erlangen, and Berlin. Schelling's philosophy developed through five stages:
      1. Subjective Idealism. Schelling's earlest important writings appeared while he was at Jena, where first he studied under Fichte and in 1798 became a member of the faculty. In this stage, he followed Fichte's thought which is apparent in the title of a work published 1795, Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism, where Dogmatism being represented by Spinoza and Criticism by Fichte. Also the same year there appeared his On the Ego as Principle of Philosophy. He insisted that the ultimate ground of our knowledge can lie only in the Ego; so he tried to deduce nature from the essence of the Ego. Soon, however, he began to oppose mind and matter, and to regard the Ego as having first produced matter and late become conscious of itself in mind. He then viewed the various forms of organic life beneath man as successive stages in which development takes place.
      2. The Philosophy of Nature. In this stage, beginning after Fichte left Jena in 1799, Schelling began to be more independent in his thinking. Although Fichte's thought formed a point of departure for his reflections, Schelling very soon showed the independence of mind. In particular, he was dissatisfied with Fichte's view of Nature as being simply an instrument for moral action. And his own view of Nature as an immediate manifestation of the Absolute, as a self-organizing dynamic and teleological system which moves upward to the emergence of consciousness and to Nature's knowledge of herself in and through men. This view found expression in his works on the philosophy of Nature. Thus in 1797, he published Ideas towards a Philosophy of Nature, in 1798 On the World-Soul and in 1799 a First Sketch of a System of a Philosophy of Nature and an Introduction to the Sketch of a Philosophy of Nature or On the Concept of Speculative Physics. Nature and mind now become more sharply contrasted. These are two different sides of philosophy. All knowledge rests upon the agreement of a subject with an object, the union of the Ego, or intelligence, and nature. We may either study nature first and show how mind arises from it ("philosophy of nature"), or we may take intelligence first and ask how objects proceed from it ("transcendental philosophy"). In his "philosophy of nature," Schelling attempts to show how mind arises in it and to indicate in an a priori manner the successive stages of an ascending evolution, without sufficient knowledge of science to make his account plausible and to show that the later and higher species have descended from earlier ones, as Lamarck was affirming and Darwin was later to try to establish. The term "speculative physics" appears in the full title of Schelling's earlier work On the World-Soul, the world-soul being said to be a hypothesis of "the higher physics." He applies the principles of attraction and repulsion to many philosophical and scientific problems. Nature is viewed as vitalistic, self-creative, and motivated by a dialectical process.
      3. Objective or Transcendental Idealism. The Philosophy of Nature is supplemented by an absolute awareness whose development is the revelation of the Absolute in history. In his "transcendental philosophy" of idealism, he tries to portray the different stages of evolution as the development of the observing mind, and in imitation of Kant he distinguishes between theoretical philosophy, practical philosophy, and the philosophy of Art. Art is the higher of the three, because in the intuition of the artist the Ego beholds itself, and the teleology that hitherto had been hidden becomes revealed to the Ego. Here Schelling is the interpreter of the Romantic movement. God is no longer for him, as for Kant and largely for Fichte, a postulate necessary for the justification of moral faith; He has become the known object of the immediate intellectual intuition of the artist. His philosophy of art, introduced at this point, finds art to be a unification of subject and object, spirit and nature. Tragedy is viewed as a collision of freedom with necessity, reconciled by the tragic hero's acceptance of punishment, bringing together the real and the ideal.
      4. The Philosophy of Identity. The Absolute becomes in this stage still more important, standing as the identity of all differences. In this stage, Spinoza and Bruno are influential. Mind and matter are at bottom identical. Even what we suppose to be dead matter is only a sleeping world which the Absolute Identity (God) may raise to life. In knowledge, truth is the form of matter; in the good, form is given to matter; in beautiful works of art, the two are absolutely blended together in a higher synthesis. Schelling for a time tried to deduce this "philosophy of identity" by mathematical method imitative of Spinoza; later he sought to work a more immediate method of intellectual intuition called "construction," by which the Absolute is seen to be in all, and all in the Absolute; the whole is expressed in every relation and object. Schelling was as unable as Spinoza has been to make clear how an Absolute that is pure identity can be related to a world of diverse persons and things.

        The ambiguities in Schelling's ever-changing philosophy led to his repudiation by Hegel, who had been his disciple and for whom he had secured a position as a colleague at Jena. Hegel stayed on at Jena after Schelling left for the university at Wurzberg in 1803. Hegel appropriated various features in Shelling's view of the Abslute and its gradual development in nature and history, and worked them over into a more coherent and systematic account which he defended by a better logical method (the dialetic). In the Phenomenology of Mind, which Hegel published in 1807, exposed the vagaries and inconsistencies in the philosophy of Schelling in a manner logically justified, but discourteous and unkind. It was evident that Hegel was far more profound and systematic thinker than Schelling. Hegel soon superseded Schelling in influence, and remained the recognized leader of philosophical thought in Germany until his own death in 1831.

      5. The Positive Philosophy. In the final stage of his thought, beginning in 1809 when he had gone to Munich, he stresses the value of mythology, and recognizes in contrast between God and the universe, and within God himself, the presence of basic polarities. In this stage, he follows in part the thought of the German Christian mystic, Jacob Boehme and Neo-platonism. Schelling now thinks of God as the primal Absolute Identity, who differentiates Himself into the world of particular beings and then returns to Himself in a higher unity. The final end of man is liberation from sin and return to God, to be accomplished through love and forgiveness. The different religions of the world are progressive stages in the revelation of God to man. So there is a certain truth even in early mythology. The highest revelation is embodied in Christianity. which has already passed through the successive stages of Catholicism and Protestantism corresponding to the apostles Peter and Paul, and is approaching the third and final stage, that of John.
      Schelling had the satisfaction of being called to Berlin in 1841 to counteract the followers of Hegel, who after the death of Hegel ten years before had fallen out among themselves, and were beginning to be viewed with disfavor. Schelling was unable to regain the position of renown which he had lost thirty years before, and the philosophy of his last period made little impression. Historically, Schelling earlier thought was an essential connecting link between Fichte and Hegel, while some of his evolutionary ideas helped to prepare the way for Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Bergson.

      Despite the shifting phases of his thought, much of the content is common throughout. Following Fichte's triadic logic of thesis-antithesis-synthesis, which he applied both to nature and history, Schelling found a three-stage development in history:

      1. the primitive age was characterized by the predominance of fate.
      2. the age of the Romans, still continuing, is characterized by a reaction of the active and voluntary aspect of man to the age of fate.
      3. the future will witness the inauguration of the third stage in which a synthesis of the two principles will occur in the balance of life in which the actual and the ideal will blend together.
      In his philosophy of mythology, Schelling holds that myth is to be understood from within, having its own laws, necessity, and reality. Futhermore, he holds that the history of a people is determined by its mythology. An accepted mythology shapes the pure creative potencies of a people. Nature as well as man, however, undergoes a mythological development.

      In his final period, the Absolute becomes "primitive will." God evolves through the persons of the Trinity, adding another instance of triadic development. The source of evil is traced to a desire for existence present in God and all else that antecedes even God, and is a first principle of all existence. Merged indissolubly in God's love, the principle becomes dissociated in men, so that the quality making possible man's freedom and creativity is also the source of his fall and his sin. Schelling affirms finally, a polarity in God, which does not disturb God's essential unity. It involves a merging of absolute and relative, necessary and contingent, eternal and temporal, potential and actual aspects. At this point God, the "Eternal Contrariety," evolves by means of the opposition between the void of nothingness and the plentitude of being, an opposition internalized in the divine nature itself.

    2. Friedrich Von Schlegel.
      The German philosopher and literateur Friedrich Von Schlegel (1772-1829), the leader of the Romantic movement in Germany, defined Romanticism as the spirit of subjectivity. Distinguishing between the spirit of objectivity, where one's personality is dominated by his material, and what one feels impelled to call the spirit of subjectivity (although the phrase seems not to have used in Schlegel), where the dominating force is the free expression of personality, Schlegel identified the first attitude with the classical period and with the enlightenment. The second attitude is that of Romanticism where genius is given free rein, dominating the objective material.

      In 1798, Schlegel underwent what appeared to be a conversion experience, and religion, God, mysticism, and the ohterworld began to fill his writings. He was attracted by the shimmering vision of reality beyond this world whose gates are not opened by critical analysis, and which one does not understand until he has experienced it. Schlegel saw fantasy or the imagination as the point of contact between within and without, as the point of contact between, the self and God. The poet is the one who illuminates and awakens man to the spark of divine within him. But in order to find one's way into the higher sphere, he must negate the earthly and finite. This requires self-scarifice, that is, death, because only from the perspective of the realm beyond does the purpose of the whole become clear. The flame of eternal life is kindled in death.

    3. Hippolyte Taine.
      The French critic and philosopher Hippolyte Taine (1828-1893) opposed Romanticism, standing as one of the chief spokesman for Positivism in the latter half of the 19th century.

END NOTES